Ferguson+pp+1-21(1)
pdf
keyboard_arrow_up
School
University of California, Berkeley *
*We aren’t endorsed by this school
Course
205
Subject
Anthropology
Date
Oct 30, 2023
Type
Pages
11
Uploaded by BarristerJay3669
The Anti-Politics Machine
"Development,"Depoliticization,
and
Bureaucratic Power in Lesotho
James
Ferguson
University of Minnesota Press
Minneapolis
London
3
I Introduction
The "development"industry in Lesotho
Lesotho is a small, land-locked country in Southern Africa, completely
surrounded by South Africa (see Figure I.1). The former British protec-
torate
of
Basutoland,Lesotho
became
independent
in
1g66.It
has
a
population of about I.3 million, an area of about 3o,ooo square kilo-
meters, and few economically significant natural resources. In
1981/2
the
Gross National
Product was
about
Ss86 million.
The
country
is
extremely mountainous, and only some ro percent of the land is arable;
the rest is suitable only for grazing of livestock.
Some gs percent of
the
population is rural
, and most of that is concentrated in the"lowlands,"a
narrow crescent of land lying along the western perimeter of the coun-
try,
conventionally
contrasted
with
the
much
larger"mountain"zone
to the east (see Figure I.2).1 Fields are cropped chiefly in maize, wheat,
and
sorghum;
livestock
include
cattle,
sheep,
and
goats.
The most
important
source
of income
for
most
households,
however,
is
wage
labor in South Africa, where perhaps
as many as 2
oo,ooo Basotho
are
employed
as
migrant
laborers(
GOL
I₉8ʒ,World
Bank
198I).
In the
period
I97s-84,this
tiny
country was receiving"development
assistance" from the following bilateral sources:2
Australia
Israel
Austria
Korea
Canada
Libya
Cyprus
The Netherlands
Denmark
Norway
Democratic Republic of Germany
Saskatchewan (Canada)
Federal Republic of Germany
Saudi Arabia
Finland
South Africa
Ghana
Sweden
Korea
Switzerland
Kuwait
Taiwan (R.O.C.)
India
United Kingdom
Iran
United States
Ireland
Introduction
Figure I.I.Lesotho-political. Source: GOL I983, World Bank 1981.
Figure 1.2.Lesotho-relief. Source: GOL 1g83, World Bank Ig8I.
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
- Access to all documents
- Unlimited textbook solutions
- 24/7 expert homework help
6
Introduction
In the same period, Lesotho was also receiving assistance from the
following
international
agencies
and non-
and quasi-governmental
organizations:2
AFL-CIO African-American Labor Center
Abu Dhabi Fund
Africa Inter-Mennonite Mission
African Development Bank
African Development Fund
African Graduate Training (U.S.)
Afro-American Institute
Agency for Personnel Service Overseas (Ireland)
Anglo-American/De Beers
Anglo-Collieries Recruiting Organization ofLesotho
Arab Bank for Economic Development in Africa
Australian Development Assistance Agency
British Council
British Leprosy Mission
Brothers ofthe Sacred Heart
CARE
Catholic ReliefService
Christian
Aid
Commonwealth Development Corporation
Commonwealth Fund for Technical Cooperation
Credit Union National Association (U.S.)
Danish Church Aid
Danish Volunteer Service
Dental Health International
Economic Commission for Africa
European Development Fund
European Economic Community
Food and Agricultural Organization ofthe U.N.
Ford Foundation
Fund for Research and Investment for the Development ofAfrica
German Volunteer Service
Goldfields (R.S.A.)
IMAP International (U.S.)
Institute for Development Management (Canada)
International Bank for Reconstruction and Development
International Civil Aviation Organization
International Cooperative Housing Development Association
International Development Association
International Extension College
Introduction
International Labour Organization
International Monetary Fund
International Potato Production Centre
International Telecommunications Union
International Trade Centre
International Volunteer Service
Meals for Millions Foundation (U.S.)
Mennonite Central Committee
Mine Labour Organization
Near East Foundation
Netherlands Organization for International Relations
OPEC
Overseas Development Institute (U.K.)
Oxford Committee for Famine Relief(U.K.)
Save the Children Fund
Seventh-Day Adventist World Service
Sisters ofthe Holy Names ofJesus and Mary
South African Mohair Board
South African Wool Board
United Nations Capital Development Fund
United Nations Fund for Population Activities
United Nations Human Habitat and Settlement Fund
U.S. Peace Corps
Unitarian Service Committee ofCanada
United Methodist Committee on Relief
United Nations Children's Emergency Fund
United Nations Development Programme
United Nations Volunteers
Volunteer Development Corporation
World Food Programme
World Health Organization
World Rehabilitation Fund
World University Service
Reading a list like this, or even walking down the streets of Lesotho's
capital city of Maseru amidst the cosmopolitan-swarm of expatriate
"experts,"one can hardly help posing the question: what is this all
about? What is this massive internationalist intervention, aimed at a
country that surely does
not
appear to be of especially greateconomic or
strategic importance? From the mid I97os on,Lesotho has received"a
disproportionate volume of a
id,"according
to
one
source(Wellings
198y:496),"most
of which
was disbursed on astonishingly generous
Introduction
terms."In
I979,
Lesotho received
some
S64
million
in
"official
de-
velopment
assistance,"according
to
the
World
Bank
(198I:I64-5),
or
about $49 for every man, woman, and child in the country-more, that
is,(on a per capita basis) than Somalia, Ethiopia, or the Sudan, and more
than Chad and Mali put together. The purpose of this aid is ostensibly to
alleviate poverty, to increase economic output, and to reduce "depen-
dence"on
South
Africa.
Its
dispersal has given rise to a substantial
"development"industry
in
Lesotho, employing
expatriate consultants
and"experts"by
the
hundreds,
and
churning
out
plans,programs,
and,
most of all, paper, at an astonishing rate.3
"
Development
assistance"
has been used for many things, of course;
but
a
large
amount
of
it
has
gone
into"projects,"especially"rural
development
projects.”
A 1977 official report (FAO I977) listed over
20o rural development schemes in Lesotho; nine of these were large,
expensive"area-based"projects
focusing
on
agricultural
development.
Yet
,if all observers of Lesotho's"
development
"agree
on
one thing,it is
that "the history of development projects in Lesotho is one of almost
unremitting
failure
to
achieve
their
objectives”(Murray
198I:19).
Again and again development projects in Lesotho are launched, and
again and again they fail; but no matter how many times this happens
there always seems to be someone ready to try again with yet another
project.For
the"development"industry
in
Lesotho,"failure"appears
to be the norm.
There is reason to believe that this situation may not be unique to
Lesotho.
It
is
true
that
Lesotho
has
a
high
concentration
of
"de-
velopment assistance," but many other, equally unlikely looking Afri-
can
countries have
concentrations
as high
or higher than Lesotho's.
Through
Africa=indeed, through the
Third World-one
seems to
find
closely
analogous
or-even
identical
"development"
institutions,
and
along
with
them
often
a
common
discourse
and
the
same
way
of
defining
"
problems
,"a
common
pool
of"experts,"and
a
common
stock
of expertise. The "development industry"is apparently a
global
phenomenon,
and there is no reason to think that the "development"
intervention in Lesotho, even if an extreme case, is entirely different in
kind from similar interventions elsewhere in the world. Even the par-
ticular
"development"initiatives
promoted
in
Lesotho
may
only
be
specific
examples
of a
more
general
model."Rural
development"pro-
jects are to be found scattered liberally across the African continent and
beyond; and,in nearly every case, these projects seem on inspection to
be planned, implemented, and justifed in very nearly the same way as
8
Introduction
they are in Lesotho. What is more, these projects
seem
to "
fail
"
with
almost the same
astonishing
regularity that
they
do in
Lesotho.
As
Williams(198I:I6-I7)
notes,"rural
development
does
not
usually
achieve its objectives";"By any criteria, successful projects have been
the exception rather than the rule."
This book will attempt to make a contribution to the
understanding
of
the
"
development
"industry
in
Lesotho
by
exploring
in
detail the
conceptualization,
planning,
and implementation
of
one"rural
de-
velopment
project,"the
Thaba-Tseka
Project,
funded
chiefly
by
the
World
Bank
and
the
Canadian
International
Development
Agency
(
CIDA
). To the extent that this single project may be seen as part of a
larger - indeed, global - apparatus, the study may have some wider
relevance in an understanding of what this "development"apparatus is
all about, and in providing a concrete demonstration of what is does,
how it does it, and why.
The literature
But, before moving on to present the research findings, it is helpful to
make explicit some theoretical points of departure. In doing this, it is
useful
to begin by
considering the
scholarly
literature
on
"develop-
ment"and"development"agencies,
and
explaining
how
this
study
relates to it.
The question of how societies change-
or
,
if
one
prefers,
"
develop"-is
not really the issue
here, and I do not propose to address
the enormous literature relating to social and historical transformation;
the question
here concerns
"development"
as
a social entity
in
its own
right:
the
set
of"development"institutions,
agencies,
and ideologies
peculiar to our own
age. The discussion that foliows thus leaves to one
side the enormous literature concerned with understanding social trans-
formations, and concentrates on
the relatively sparse scholarly
literature
that aims to understand,
explain
, analyze, or make
sense
of the"
de-
velopment”industry
itself.
The literature on this point is divided, along sharply ideological lines,
into two main camps. On the one hand are those who, either as insiders
or
as
sympathetic
outsiders,
see
"
development
"
planning
and
"
de-
velopment"agencies as part of a great collective effort to fight poverty,
raise standards of living, and promote one or another
version
of pro-
gress
. For these writers, of whom a figure like
Gunnar Myrdalis
perhaps
a
paradigmatic
example
,
the
"development"apparatus
is
to
be
9
Introduction
understood as a tool at the disposal of a planner, who will need good
advice on how to make best use of it. It goes without saying for these
writers that a "development" agency is at least potentially a force for
beneficial change;the reason for analyzing such an entity is to enableit
to perform better, to avoid failures and to maximize its success. From
broad, reflective works like Hirschman's Development Projects Ob-
served to detailed, empirical studies such as Morss etal.(1976)
,thefocus
remains technicaland managerial.In this literature, the
"
development
"
apparatus is scrutinized at all levels, but always with an eye to locating
what goes"wrong,"why,and howit can befixed. Even the broaderand
more speculative discussions in this vein remain a-brand of policy
science, locating problems and arriving at recommendations addressed
to planners within
"
development
"
institutions.4
Most anthropologists who have explicitly made development agen-
cies or projects the focus oftheir research fall into this camp. An early
example is Reining's analysis (1966) ofthe Gezira cotton scheme. For
Lesotho, there is Wallman's important study (1g69) in a similar vein.
Several writers on "development anthropology"have urged that many
problems encountered by."development agencies can only be solved
by taking an anthropological view of the"development"institutions
themselves
(Brokensha et. al. 198o, Cochrane 1971). More recently
Chambers(198o) has written on"experts"in rural Africa,while Hoben
(198o) has published a policy-oriented anthropological analysis on the
functioning ofthe USAID bureaucracy.
The most ambitious atempt to date at an anthropological analysis of
"development”as an international institution is Robertson's Peopleand
the State: An
Anthropology
of Planned Development (
1984
).
Although
more sensitive than many to the politically loaded contexts in which
"development"planning may be embedded, Robertson, too, ends up
falling comfortably within the tradition of seeing the "development"
apparatus as a practical tool for the solution of universa
l problems.
"Development'planning, for Robertson, is to be understood as“man-
kind's most ambitious collective enterprise”(1984:I), the activity of
nation
-
states attempting
to
bring
into being"
ideal
worlds.""Develop-
ment"agencies,in this view, areleft with the task oftrying to implement
these often unrealistic plans. The role ofthe scholar in this apparatus is
to try to see to itthat the 'ideal worlds" pursued by states are consistent
with what we know about how real societies actually work, so that
"development"planning can set itself objectives capable of being re-
alized."Development"projects are thus to be interpreted aslamentably
Io
Introduction
inexpert attempts by society to remake itself; while, for social science,
utopian theorizing is apparently the order ofthe day.
The second approach to conceptualizing "development"institutions
is the radical critique associated with neo-Marxism and dependency
theory.5 Authors representing this tradition do not generally spend
much time discussing the international "development"establishment,
and have little regard for those "Fabians" like Myrdal who put them-
selves at its service. The issue is generally treated in the context of a
political denunciation along the following lines: If (and this is the first
postulate of neo-Marxism) capitalism is not a progressive force but a
reactionary one in the Third World -not the cause of development but
the obstacle to it, not the cure for poverty but the cause ofit-then a
capitalist-run development project is a fundamentally contradictory
endeavor. If it is meant to promote imperial capitalism (and why else
would capitalist institutions like the World Bank, USAID, etc.do it?)
then it cannot at the same time be an instrument for development, at
least not for"real"development.The purpose of a development project
is to aid capitalist exploitation in a given country, these writers argue,
either by incorporating new territories into the world system, or work-
ing against radical socialchange, or bribing nationalelites,or mystifying
the
realinternationalrelationships, or any number of other mechanisms
which seem to be called up as needed on an ad hoc basis.The implication
isthat
any concrete aid program, beit an early 196os"big dam"project,
late 197os"basicneeds,"or whatever,is explained,almostby defnition,
by the "logic
of capital."6
A.related argument has been advanced by Lappe and Collins (1979,
Lappe et al.I98o), who reason that:(1) poverty is notaswigenerisfactor
a consequence ofglobal scarcity but only a symptom ofpowerlessness;
(2)internationalaid projects by their very nature, whoever they claim to
"target,"do not make the radical changes in political and economic
structures that could alone empower the poor;therefore (3) aid projects
cannot be expected to help to eradicate poverty sincethey only reinforce
the system which in the first place causes the poverty
.Lappe and Collins
offer a powerful and well-documented political argument, but it does
not help us to understand the different forms of intervention that have
aver the years been practiced under the name of"development"since it
gives only a negative characterization of what an aid project (or,by
implication, any national or international maneuver that falls short of
posing a fundamental challenge to the entrenched system of exploi-
tation) does: it does not help the hungry as it is supposed to, it only
II
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
- Access to all documents
- Unlimited textbook solutions
- 24/7 expert homework help
Introduction
strengthens the powerful. The argument
is
still
organized
around
the
politically naive
question
:"Do aid
programs
really
help
poor
people?"
Thus attention is paid to what aid projects do, but once again only to
show that they "fail,"i.e. that they do not reduce hunger, or to claim
that they are"showcase projects,"
which"distract
our attention
"
from
the"overriding functions"of development
aid
, functions
specified only
as strategic and imperialistic (Lappe et al. Ig8o:I22).
We
have,
then,
an
important
body
of
recent
literature,
and
two
fundamentally
opposed
notions
of
how
to
interpret
the
"development"
apparatus.
Which
position
will
the
present
study
take?
This question can perhaps be illuminated by making a
comparison
with Paul Willis's important book Learning to Labour: How Working
Class Kids Get
Working Class Jobs.
Willis's book encounters an enor-
mous body of literature, the “education” literature, and finds that
literature divisible into two camps based on the authors' attitudes
toward
the
fundamental
nature
or
purpose
of the
institution"the
school."The liberal, from the eighteenth century onward, regards the
public school as an instrument for creating an enlightened, egalitarian
society, a society with equal opportunity for all. Thus the question in
recent times has been how to use and reform schools so that they can
help to eradicate the economic, social, and political gaps which separate
whites and blacks, workers and middle-class, men and women.7 Against
this view has arisen a Marxist critique which argues that, contrary to the
claim that schools are either actually or potentially forces for democratic
ends, these institutions were established from the very beginning to
achieve the opposite. Schools, the Marxists argue, were established by
the capitalist state in order to reproduce labor power for an industrial
order whose jobs were organized hierarchically. They are not tools for
engineering social equality - they are by nature mechanisms for repro-
ducing labor power for a class society. This is known as the "reproduc-
tion"thesis.8
Willis, for his part,
rejects the Liberal
argument as
politically naive
and takes it as a fact that class
relations are
reproduced under capitalism
(working-class kids do get working-class jobs) and that the schools play
an important part in this. But he moves beyond"reproduction theory"
by refusing to be satisfied with this. Yes, reproduction occurs through
(in part)the school, but"for all we are told of how this actually happens,
schools may as well be 'black boxes'."This, he observes, is neither
theoretically nor politically adequate. Instead, Willis offers
a detailed
ethnography of what actually happens when
the
apparatus of
schooling
I2
Introduction
is brought to bear on a group
of working
-
class kids. He finds that there
is no mechanistic imprinting of the characteristics required by the
capitalist state on its passive victims, as the reproduction theory might
suggest, but rather an ongoing battle between school power on the one
hand, and resistance based in working-class culture on the other.And it
is, ironically, through this resistance that the task of"reproduction"is
eventually accomplished. The resistance provoked by schooling is thus
an essential part of the explanation for how labor power is reproduced.
The school indeed accomplishes the task assigned to it in reproduction
theory, but in an unexpected and startling way, a way
which underlines
the ambiguities of resistance and the scope for choiceand politicalaction
in a world that is always structured but never determined.
Similarly, when one reads much of the literature on the "develop-
ment"industry, one finds oneself doubly dissatisfied=with the liberals,
whose only concern seems to
be
with directing or reforming an
insti-
tution
whose fundamental
beneficence they
take as given-and with the
neo-Marxists, who seem satisfied to establish that the institutions of
"development" are part of a
fundamentally imperialistic
relation
be-
tween center and periphery and take the matter
to be thus settled.
But the matter is not settled, any more than the issue of the school is
settled by showing that the schools are part of a system of reproduction
of labor power. For if
, as
the neo-Marxists
argue,
an international
development project is to be
understood not as a humanitarian attempt
to overcome poverty but as
an important
instrument of imperial and
class-based control, then one ought to be interested enough to look and
see how this control is effected
. One cannot, as Willis rightly notes,
expect things to simply snap into place through mysterious"black box"
mechanisms
simply because
Capital"needs"for
them to
do
so.
A
structure always reproduces itself through
a
process,
and through
a
struggle; and the sense of a structure, Willis shows, can only be grasped
through
that sometimes
surprising and
ironic process, and never by
merely
labeling the structure with the
name of
those whose interests it
serves.
A few recent studies of"rural development"make an important start
toward
such
an
understanding
of the
"development"apparatus
by
looking at the interventions of "development"agencies not for what
they don't do or might do, but for what they do. The edited collection
by Heyer, Roberts, and Williams (198r), for instance, is not much
interested in the polemics over whether or not "rural development"is
really a matter of "helping the poor," or as one formula (Chambers
I3
Introduction
I₉83) has it,"putting the last first."
They
quickly dismiss this liberal
viey, noting that empirically there "appears to be litle foundation for
the assumption that the activities of rural development programmeslead
to the improvement of the welfare of the rural population, let alone the
ruralpoor”(Heyer et al.I₉8I: Io),Butthis is seen as neither surprising
nor especially iluminating; after all, as Keith Griffin remarks in his
refreshing preface to the volume,"More often than not,the government
has
repreented
interests other than those of
the
rural
poor and it is
hardly
surprising, therefore, that public intervention has in practic
e
been harmful to the majority of the rural people rather than beneficial”
(Heyer et al. 198r: vii). For Heyer et al, this is not the main issue; the
ta
sk is not to denounce the"rural development"establishme
ntfor
what
itisnot,butto
analyzeit-notinterms
of
its
own
proclamations,butasa
social institution in its own right, supported and maintained not by
“capitalism”in the abstract, but by historically specifie political and
economic
interests
in each
case. This attempt to see "rural develop-
ment"interventions as real historical events, susceptible of the same sort
of poltical-economic explanation as any others, is found in several
recent works in addition to the volume by Heyer, Roberts, and Williams
(198r),including
Williams(1976,198sa,1986),Beckman(1977),
Bern-
stein (1977, 1979) and the articles in Galli(1981).
It is an important advance to have moved the discussion-on the
"
development" industry beyond the
widespread ideological preoccu-
pation withthe question of whether itisto be considereda"good
thing"
or
a"
bad
thing"a benevolent force to be reformed
or
an exploitative
maneuver to
be
denounced.
Insofar as works in the political economy
tradition like Heyer et al.(198I) and Galli(198I) insist that
"rural
development" is the name for a complex set of institutions and initiat-
ives
encompassing
"multiple,
and
often
contradictory,
interests"
(Heyer et al.198r: 12),they are in full agreement with the aims of the
present work. However,the way in which most of these authors have
gone about analyzing the complex reality they have identified as "rural
development" is signifcantly different from
the approach that wil
be
taken here.
First of all, the political economists are often too quick to impute an
economic function to "development" projects, and to accepttheprem-
isethat a"development"projectis primarily adevicefor bringing about
a.particular sort of economie transformation - a transformation vari-
ously
glossed
as
"capitalist
penetration,""commoditization,”"capi-
talist
development,”"the
expansion
of
the
capitalist
mode
of
I4
Introduction
production,"etc. In this vein, for instance, Beckman (1977:3)claims
that rural"development" projects
"serve to
subject peasants to the
imperative of producing for an external market under monopolistic
relations of exchange," while Bernstein (1977: 6s) declares as if self-
evident
that rural"development"projects
"operate objectively to in-
corporate the peasantry further into commodity relations."
It is clear in reading scholarly literature on"development"that
the
word"development" is used to refer to at least two quite separat
e
things
. On the one hand,"development"is used to mean the process of
transition or transformation toward a modern, capitalist, industrial
economy-
"modernization
,""capitalist
development
,""
the
develop
-
ment of the forces of production,"etc. The second meaning, much in
vogue from the mid I97os onward,
defines itself in terms of"quality
of
life"and"standard
of living,"and refers to the
red
uction
or
amelior-
ation of poverty and material want
.
The directionality
implied
in
the
word"development" is in this usage no longer historical, but moral
.
"Development"is no longer a movement in history, but an activity, a
social program, a war on poverty on a global scale.
Liberals
and"de
-
velopment" bureaucrats regularly conflate these two
meanings,
im-
plicitly equating"modernization"with the elimination or alleviation
of
poverty.
Against this view, the critics insist that the two are different,e.
that
capitalist development in Africa is very often the cause of poverty
and not its cure, and that it is usually not in the interests of the rural poor
at all. For the liberal, a rural development project brings"develop-
ment,"in one or both of the above senses, and that is all to the good.For
the critics discussed above, a rural development project is part of "the
expansion of the capitalist mode of production"-“capitalist develop-
ment"-which is often not so good at all for the poor"peasants."Class
formation, growing inequality and landlessness, decreased self-suff-
ciency,and increased poverty are commonly cited results. But
the point
to be emphasized here is that both the "development"establishment
and many of its most articulate critics accept that a rural
development
project does in fact - for better or worse - bring about some sort of
"development," some sort of economic transformation toward a well
-
defined end point
.9
The second
major
point to be
emphasized in
the political
economy
t
ype-of approach
of the writers under discussion is the extremely
important place occupied in their analyses
by"interests
."The
existence
and structure of the"development"industry, and what happens when it
is deployed in various different settings, are analyzed by identifying the
I5
Introduction
various interests that are involved. A"development"project is taken to
be explained when all the different interests behind it have been sorted
out
and
made
spec
ific
.
The interested agents may be classes, national
governments,
or individuals, but whoever the actors are taken to be,
explanation takes the form of attributing an-event or a structure to a
particular
constellation
of
“
interests.”
With regard to both of these points, the approach
taken here will be
rather different, for both empirical and theoretical reasons. Empirically,
"development"projects
in
Lesotho
do
not
generally bring
about
any
significant reduction in poverty, but neither do they characteristically
introduce any new relations of production (capitalist or otherwise), or
bring
about
signifcant
economic transformations.
They
do not bring
about"development"in
either
of the
two
senses identified
above, nor
are
they
set
up in such a way that the
y ever
could, as will be seen in the
chapters that follow. For this reason, it seems a mistake to interpret
them as“part of the historicalexpansion of capitalism”(Galli
198I:x)or
as elements in a global strategy for controlling or capitalizing peasant
production,
a
solution
to"the
peasant
problem"(Williams
I98r).
At the same time - again, empirically - there is no easy congruence
between the"objective
interests"of
the various parties and the stream of
events which emerges. Unquestionably, there are a number of different
interested parties whose interests can be identified and made explicit.
The
interests
of the
World
Bank
in promoting"development"projects
have
been
well
analyzed
by
Williams(198I),
Payer(1983)and
others;
the
economic
stake
of a
country
like
Canada
in"development"inter-
ventions in Africa has been made clear by Freeman(1984). But while itis
certainly relevant to know, for instance, that the World Bank has an
interest in boosting productio
n and export of cash crops for the external
market, and that industrialized states without historic links to an area
may
sponsor"development"projects
as
a way
of breaking
into
other-
wise inaccessible markets,it remains impossible to simply read off actual
events from these known interests as if the one werea simple effect of the
other.
One
may know,
for
instance, that
Canada
sponsored
a rural
development project in Thaba-Tseka, and one may know as well that the
Canadian government has an interest in promoting rural development
programs because it helps Canadian corporations to find export markets
for farm machinery (among other things), but this pairing of facts does
not
constitute an acceptable
level of explanation, and in fact leaves many
of the empirical details of the Canadian role absolutely mysterious.
Theoretically, as well, the approach reviewed above is inadequate to
I6
Introduction
the task this study sets itself. The most important theoretical differences
will be brought out in the following section.
Some
theoretical
points
of
departure
The first issue to be raised, perhaps, is that the present study is an
anthropological
one.
Unlike many anthropological works on"develop
-
ment," this one takes as its primary object not the people to be"de-
veloped,"but the apparatus that is to do the "developing."This is not
principally a book about the Basotho
people, or even
about
Lesotho;it
is
principally a book about the
operation
of
the
international"de-
velopment"apparatus
in
a
particular
setting
.
To
take
on
the
task
of
looking
at
the"development"
apparatus
anthropologically
is to insist on a particular sort of approach to the
material. As
an
anthropologist,
one
cannot
assume
,
for
instance,as
many political economists do, that
a
structure
simply
and rationa
lly
"represents"or"expresses"a
set
of
"objective
interests";
one
knows
that
structures
are
multi-layered, polyvalent,
and
often
contradictory,
and that economic functions and
"objective interests" are always lo-
cated within other, encompassing structures that may be invisible even
to those who inhabit them.The interests may be clear, and the intentions
as
well;
but
the
anthropologist
cannot
take
"planning"at
its
word.
Instead of ascribing events and institutions to
the projects
of various
actors,
an
anthropological
approach
must
demote
the
plans
and
in-
tentions of even the most powerful interests to the status of an interest-
ing
problem,
one
level
among
many
others,
for
the
anthropologist
knows well how easily structures can take on lives of their own that soon
enough
overtake
intentional practices. Whatever
interests may be
at
work,
and whatever they may think they
are
doing, they
can
only
operate through a complex set of social and cultural structures so deeply
embedded and so ill-perceived that the outcome may be only a baroque
and unrecognizable transformation
of the
original intention. The ap-
proach adopted here treats such an outcome as neither an inexplicable
mistake, nor the trace of a yet-undiscovered intention, but as a riddle, a
problem to be solved, an anthropological puzzle.
It is at this point that the issue of discourse becomes important. For
writers such as Heyer et al.(1981)and Galli (198I), official discourse on
"development"either
expresses
"true intentions
"
or
,
more often, pro-
vides an ideological screen for other, concealed intentions:"mere rhet-
oric."The bulk of"development" discourse, with all its professions of
I7
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
- Access to all documents
- Unlimited textbook solutions
- 24/7 expert homework help
Introduction
concern
for
the
rural poor and so on, is for these writers simply
a
misrepresentation
of what
the
"
development
"apparatus
is
"really"
up
to. The World Bank may talk a lot about helping poor farmers, for
instance, but in fact their funds continue to be targeted at the large,
highly capitalized farmers, at the expense of the poor. The much publi-
cized"new strategy,"then, is "largely rhetoric," serving only a mysti-
fying
function(Williams I98r).
In
the anthropological approach adopted below, the discourse
of the
"development"establishment is considered much more important than
this. It may be that much of this discourse is untrue, but that is no excuse
for dismissing
it. As Foucault(
197I, I973) has shown, discourse is a
practice
, it is structured, and
it
has real effects which are
much
more
profound
than -simply "mystification
"
.
The
thoughts and actions of
"
development"bureaucrats
are powerfully
shaped by the world
of
acceptable
statements
and
utterances within which they live; and
what
they
do
and do not do is a product-
not only of the interests of various
nations,classes, orinternational agencies, but also, and at the same time,
of a working out of this complex structure of knowledge
. Instead of
ignoring the orderly field of statements produced by the "development"
apparatus on the grounds that the statements are ideological, the study
below takes this field as its point of departure for an exploration of the
way in which "development"initiatives are produced
and
put
into
practice
.
It should be clear from the above that
the approach to be taken to the
problem of the
"development"industry in Lesotho will
be, in keeping
with the anthropological approach,
"decentered
"-that
is,
it will locate
the intelligibility of a series of events and transformations not in the
intentions guiding the actions of one or more animating
subjects
, butin
the
systematic nature of the social
reality
which
results from those
actions. Seeing a"development"project as the simple projection of the
“interest”of a subject (the World Bank, Canada, Capital, Imperialism)
ignores the non- and counter-intentionality of structural production,
and is in this way profoundly non-anthropological. As in the case of
Willis's treatment of the schooling apparatus (198I),
one must entertain
the possibility that the "development" apparatus in Lesotho may
do
what
it does, not at the bidding of some knowing and powerful subiect
who is
making it all
happen
, but behind the backs of or against the wills
of even the most powerful actors.
But this is not to say that such
institutions do not represent an exercise of power; only that power is
not to be
embodied in the person of a"
powerful
"
subject.
A“
de-
I8
Introduction
velopment" project may very well serve power, but in a different way
than any ofthe"powerful"actors imagined;it may only wind up,in the
end,"
turning
out" to serve power.
At this point, the theoretical approach of the present work links up
with another important body of literature, closely associated with the
work of Foucaul (1979, 198oa, 198ob). Using a decentered conception
of power
, a number of recent studies (e.g. Foucault 1979
,
198ca, Don-
zelot 1979, Pasquino 1978, Procacci I978, Jones and Williamson 1979)
have shown how the
outcomes ofplanned
social interventions can end
up coming together into powerful constellations of control that were
never intended and in some cases never even recognized, but are all the
more
effective
for
being
"
subieetless."
This theoretical
innovation
makes possible adiferent way of
connecting outcomes with power
,one
that avoids gwing a cenral place to any acior orentity conceived asa
'powerful"
subject.
Perhaps
the best example of
this
kind
of
analysis is
Foucault's
"
gene-
alogy" of the prison (1979).The prison,Foucault shows, was created as
a“correctional”institution. It was intended to imprint on the inmates
the
qualities
of good
citizenship: to make criminals into honest, hard
working,law abiding individuals,who could return to a"normal" place
in society. This idea of"rehabilitation"was behind the establishment of
modern prisons throughout the world, and it continues to be offered as
the chief justification for maintaining them and, from time to time,
reforming them. Butit is obvious upon inspection;according to Fou.
cault, that prisons do not in fact"reform"
criminals; that, on the
cantrary, they-make nearly impossible that return to"normality"that
they have always claimed to produce, and that, instead of eliminating
criminality, they seem rather to produce and intensify it
within
a
well defined strata
of
"delinquents
."While
such
a result must be con-
ccived as a"failure" from the point of view of the planners'intentions,
theresult has quite a different character when apprehended as part of a
different "strategy."For the constitution of a class of "delinquents,"
Foucault argues, turned oute to be very useful in taming "
popular
ilegalities" and transforming the political
fact of illegality into the
suasi-medical one of pathological
delinquency
." By
diferentiating
ilegalities,and by turning one uniquely wel-supervised and controlled
s
of violators against the
others,
the
prison did
end
up serving
apart
of a system of social control, but in a very different way
than
its
planners
had
envisioned
.
"If
this is
the
case," Foucault
writes:
I9
2I
20
Introduction
the prison,
apparently "failing", does not miss its target
; on the
contrary, it reaches it, in so far as it gives rise to one particular form
of illegality in the midst of others, which it is able to isolate, to place
in full light and to organize as a relatively enclosed, but penetrable,
milieu...
For the observation that prison fails to eliminate crime, one should
perhaps substitute the hypothesis that prison has succeeded extremely
well in producing delinquency, a specific type, a politically or
economically
less
dangerous-and,
on
occasion,
usable
-form
of
illegality; in producing delinquents, in an apparently marginal, but in
fact centrally supervised milieu; in producing the delinquent
as
a
pathologized subject ... So successful has the prison been that, after a
century and a half of 'failures', the prison still exists, producing the
same results, and there is the greatest reluctance to dispense with it.
(Foucault 1979:276-7)
The point to be taken from the above argument is only that
planned
interventions may produce unintended outcomes that end up, all the
same,
incorporated
into
anonymous
constellations
of
control-author-
less"strategies,"in
Foucault's
sense
(1979, I98ob)-that turn out in the
end to have a kind of politicalintelligibility. This is only another way of
approaching the problem noted by Willis (198I)in his discussion of the
school cited above: the most important political effects of a planned
intervention may occur unconsciously, behind the backs or against the
wills of the "planners" who may seem to be running the show.
This will
turn
out to be
one
of the key problems raised by the
operation
ofthe"development"apparatus
in
Lesotho,
and
the
approach
that is adopted owes much to the literature so briefly discussed above.
The
complex relation between the intentionality of planning and the
strategic intelligibility of outcomes is perhaps the single most important
theme winding through the pages that follow.As this theme appears and
reappears in the chapters below, one cardinal principle will beillustrated
again and again: intentional plans are always important, but never in
quite the way the planners imagined. In the pages that follow, I will try
to
show how, in the case of a development project in Lesotho, in-
tentional plans interacted with unacknowledged structures and chance
events to produce unintended outcomes which turn out to be intelligible
not only as the unforeseen effects of an intendedintervention, but also as
the
unlikely
instruments
of
an
unplotted
strategy.
Specifically,
the
remaining chapters will show how outcomes that at first appear as mere
"side
effects"
of an
unsuccessful
attempt
to
engineer
an
economic
Introduction
transformation become legible in another perspective as unintended yet
instrumental
elements in
a
resultant
constellation
that has the effect of
expanding
the exercise of a particular sort of state power while
simul-
taneously exerting
a
powerful depoliticizing effect.itis this
unauthored
resultant constellation that
I
call
"theanti-politicsmachine
,
"
for
reasons
that I hope will in the end become clear. The remaining chapters aim to
explore
how
such
an
unlikely
"machine"
works,
and
to
understand
better what it does.
Related Documents
Recommended textbooks for you
Essentials of Physical Anthropology (Third Editio...
Anthropology
ISBN:9780393938661
Author:Clark Spencer Larsen
Publisher:W. W. Norton & Company
Recommended textbooks for you
- Essentials of Physical Anthropology (Third Editio...AnthropologyISBN:9780393938661Author:Clark Spencer LarsenPublisher:W. W. Norton & Company
Essentials of Physical Anthropology (Third Editio...
Anthropology
ISBN:9780393938661
Author:Clark Spencer Larsen
Publisher:W. W. Norton & Company
Browse Popular Homework Q&A
Q: A 27-inch by 72-inch piece of cardboard is used to make an open-top box by removing a square from…
Q: The nation's commodity terms of trade times the productivity index in its export sector gives the…
Q: At a restaurant, the density function for the time a customer has to wait before being seated is…
Q: n linux code:
Write command line for the following. Do submit only one cmd for each problem. ie One…
Q: Say that an object of mass is pushed by a system of two radial Forces and moves with a constant…
Q: GDP is a strong measure of the health of the economy, and it’s among the most important and widely…
Q: A
Which of the following phase changes represents the phase change in which e
the system, and why?
B…
Q: . If cos 0 =
0.8 and 270°<<360°, find the exact value of sin 20.
Q: 10- For the data in Problem 10-5, assume that the optimistic probability is 20%, the most likely is…
Q: The principal P is borrowed at a simple interest rate r for a period of time t. Find the simple…
Q: Consider a drug that is used to help prevent blood clots in certain patients. In clinical trials,…
Q: 1. Name these compounds:
но снсH,он
ÓCH3
a)
b)
косҫнсн он
OCH3
d)
сно ансњон
OCH3
CH,CH₂NHECHCH₂OH…
Q: downward deflection is
in. I
Q: Social interactions in a week: x
6
7
15
19
22
27
33
36
44
46
Number of college students: f
15…
Q: In a survey of 100 college students, 35 were registered in College Algebra, 52 were
registered in…
Q: 2. The function f is differentiable on the
interval (0, 4). If f(1) = 1 and f(3) = 7,
then there is…
Q: can you show the expermiental r calculations in detail
Q: Find the volume of the solid obtained by rotating the region
bounded by the given curves about the…
Q: A=
Consider the following compounds
D-HOCH CH
B.
E =
C =
F=
a) Which one(s) would give a positive…
Q: For the sequence, determine if the divergence test applies and either state that lim a, does not…
Q: Find the area of the surface.
The part of the plane
x + 2y + 3z = 1
that lies inside the cylinder…
Q: its peak. From launch to peak 1.7 elapsed. from peak to impact it fell 29M. Determine the speed of…
Q: Sidney invests $500 in one account earning 1% interest, and $1000 in another account. If, after two…
Q: In 2011, a local Dairy Queen had $750,000 in sales. In 2012, Dairy Queen’s sales were up 15%. What…
Q: Determine whether the integral is convergent or divergent. If it is convergent, evaluate it. (If the…