Internal and External Acts; The Morality of Emotions
docx
keyboard_arrow_up
School
University of Mary *
*We aren’t endorsed by this school
Course
308
Subject
Philosophy
Date
Feb 20, 2024
Type
docx
Pages
3
Uploaded by MegaKoalaPerson1061
Ethics
INTRODUCTION:
Moral evaluations pertain to things that we do.
When we think of human actions
that are subject to moral appraisal, we tend to think of them as primarily consisting
of outward performances
or what Aquinas calls external acts. It is wrong to cheat
on exams, steal, and perform torture. But restricting moral evaluations solely to our
external actions leaves a whole array of human performances untouched. Along
with our external acts, we also execute a number of inward performances
or what
Aquinas calls internal acts
. We have wants, desires, form beliefs, and ultimately
form intentions or will
to perform external acts. All of these internal acts can be
subject to moral evaluation. (This is why we confess that they have sinned against
God in ‘thought, word and deed.’) In the assigned reading, Aquinas focuses on the
internal act of willing
. When acting voluntarily, we execute outward performances
only because we will to do so. As a result, it is tempting to think that when we are
morally evaluating human behaviors, we are really just evaluating internal acts, -
i.e.
what we want, desire, and ultimately will to do. But is this really the case? Is
forming the intention to cheat on an exam just as wrong as the actual cheating? As
we will see, Aquinas makes several key distinctions that will help us to answer this
question.
Also, suppose that that our internal acts such as our intentions and attitudes are
subject to moral appraisal. Is the same true for our emotions? Are our emotions
exempt from moral appraisal or are we responsible for them as well? If so, to what
degree are we responsible for them?
It is commonly said that we “cannot help the way we feel.” This statement implies
that we are not responsible for our emotions because they are out of our control.
That is, although they may be disordered, they are merely sinful, and not morally
wrong, because they are not voluntary. Is this true? Do we have the requisite
control over our emotions to make them proper objects of moral appraisal?
In the assigned reading, Aquinas once again provides a helpful distinction that helps
to explain when and why we are responsible for our emotions. He also clarifies
when our emotions affect the moral goodness or badness of our actions. Jensen
helps us to further think about the proper relation between our emotions and
reason.
ASSIGNED READING:
On Evil,
Q.II, A.2, ‘Does Sin Consist Solely of the Will’s Act?’, pp. 95-100
-
focus on Objections
6, and 8, the Answer
, and Replies to Objections 6 and 8
Stephen Jensen, “On Reason and the Emotions” [Canvas]
On Evil,
Q. III, A. 11, “Does Weakness Make Sin Less or More Serious?” (pp. 175-176)
-
focus on the Answer
and Objections 1 & 3
REFLECTION QUESTIONS:
1)
What was the most important thing that you learned from our previous class session? Why do you find this important?
The definition of evil and good and the conditions that a human act must meet in order to be the proper object of moral evaluation. 2)
What is one question you have that stems from the previous class session or reading?
Clarification of species. READING QUESTIONS:
1)
According to Aquinas, is the person who plans a murder, but never has
the opportunity to carry it out more or less to blame than the person
who plans and commits a murder? Why?
According to Aquinas, both the person who plans and commit the murder are
equally to blame. This is because the intention to commit murder and the act of
committing a murder are both
considered evil.
2)
According to Jensen, what is the role of reason in ethics?
Reason plays a critical role in ethics, as it is the vehicle by which we as humans
are able to reconcile what is good or evil in various acts.
3)
Explain Jensen’s account of rationalization.
Jensen states that rationalization is when you attempt to “soothe” your
conscience with quasi-moral justifications. He states that rationalization is a
means of deception, as you are engaging in faux-reasoning to at least give the
appearance of following moral judgements. Jensen claims that rationalization has
3 steps: 1) recognizing what is truly right & wrong; 2) we desire what is wrong;
and, 3) we come up with quasi-moral reasons to follow our evil desires. 4)
Explain Jensen’s account of the relation between reason and emotions.
Jensen states that reason is a “knowing power”—taking in the world, perceiving
the way things are. Emotions are an “appetite”—they do not take in the world,
but move out to it. He explains that anger is a feeling toward someone, not a
judgement. He goes on to say that reason is found in humans alone, while all
animals experience emotions. 5) Explain, in your own words, the argument put forth in Q. III, A. 11,
Objection 1.
If there is any emotion involved in committing a sin, then there is
blameworthiness, making the sin greater. 6) Explain, using examples of your own, Aquinas distinction between
passions (emotions) which (i) precede the will
and those passions which
are (ii) subsequent to the will
. Passions that precede the will are those emotions that cause one to engage in
an act that creates the betterment of oneself. Passions which are subsequent to
the will, on the other hand, are emotions that cause detriment to the will.
7)
According to Aquinas, which emotions makes sin more serious, those
that precede the will or those that are consequent to it? Why? Which of
these passions makes sin less serious? Why?
Passions that are subsequent to the will create more serious sins as these are
emotions that have the capacity to create a serious detriment to our will.
Passions that precede the will have a higher chance of earning merit.
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
- Access to all documents
- Unlimited textbook solutions
- 24/7 expert homework help