AL FINAL PHI

docx

School

University of Ottawa *

*We aren’t endorsed by this school

Course

1370

Subject

Medicine

Date

Dec 6, 2023

Type

docx

Pages

5

Uploaded by ChiefTitaniumSalamander35

Report
Ashlie Leclerc 300287965 PART A: 1. The desert idea about justice means that people should get rewards or punishments based on what they do or achieve, not just because they are lucky or have a high status in society. The term means that individuals should receive fair consequences for their own decisions and behavior (desert is used as a derivative of deserve in this context). This way of thinking focuses on being responsible for yourself and depending on yourself. There are a couple of objections to this theory. Firstly, it is troublesome to determine what people really deserve. Deciding what an individual genuinely deserves can be subjective and open to interpretation. Components such as good fortune, natural abilities, and social benefits can affect a person's choices and results, making it troublesome to decide what they really merit. In expansion, it can lead to cruel and unbalanced disciplines. The desert theory can lead to disciplines that are unbalanced to the offense committed. For example, an individual who commits a minor wrongdoing may get a cruel discipline based on the conviction that they deserve it, instead of on the genuine harm caused. Finally, it does not account for systemic treacheries. The desert theory places the obligation for results exclusively on the person, without taking under consideration the effect of bigger societal and systemic components such as poverty, discrimination, and inequality. Overall, whereas the desert theory of justice has its merits, I believe it is not a good form of justice as it can be restricted in its capacity to account for the complexities of human behavior and societal components. A more nuanced approach to justice is fundamental, one that takes into consideration both a person's duty and societal context. Reference References used for inspiration: Young, Iris Marion, and Martha Nussbaum, Responsibility for Justice, Oxford Political Philosophy (2011; online edn, Oxford Academic, 1 Jan. 2011), https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195392388.001.0001 2. The rule "Worst first, first come, and hopeless second" is a principle utilized in triage situations to prioritize medical treatment and distribute resources to patients based on the seriousness of their condition. According to this principle, the most critically sick or harmed patients are given the upper most priority for treatment and resources, regardless of the order in which they arrived at the healthcare facility. This is because their condition poses the most prominent risk to their survival and requires quick medical attention. The following priority is given to patients who arrived first but have less serious conditions, then followed by those who have a small chance of survival or whose condition is considered hopeless, even if given treatment. While this principle provides a clear framework for prioritizing medical treatment, it can moreover be problematic in a few regards. One potential issue is that it may not always be clear which patients are the foremost critically sick or harmed, as there can be a significant variety in side effects and seriousness even within the same category of sickness or injury. Another concern is that this principle may not account for the potential for recuperation or the effect of treatment
on patient outcomes. In a few cases, patients who show up to be in a hopeless condition may react well to treatment and recuperate completely, whereas others who are at first steady may fall apart quickly without immediate medical assistance. 3. The sympathy rule is a regulation that would not permit healthcare providers to help their relatives and/or friends in any way they like. However, in extreme situations, for example life and death situations, it would permit them to give priority to their relatives and/or friends if needed. The sympathy rule can be considered a good rule for a few reasons. To start off, it advances reasonable and fair treatment. By disallowing healthcare providers from giving special treatment to their friends and family members, the rule helps to guarantee that all patients are treated equally and without bias. This will improve the quality of care given and advance trust within the healthcare system. In addition, it maintains professional ethics, healthcare providers are bound by professional morals to provide the finest possible care to all patients, regardless of their personal relationship. The sympathy rule strengthens this ethical commitment and guarantees that healthcare providers prioritize patient care over individual interests. Finally, it recognizes human compassion. In certain uncommon circumstances, such as life and death circumstances, healthcare providers may have a strong desire to help their loved ones. The sympathy rule recognizes this compassion and permits for some flexibility in prioritizing their cherished ones' needs, while still maintaining the commitment to provide reasonable and equal care to all patients. References used for inspiration: American Medical Association. (2016). Code of Medical Ethics Opinion 1.2.2: Treating Self or Family, https://www.ama-assn.org/system/files/code-of-medical- ethics-chapter-1.pdf, 5. Doubts on vaccine safety arose from a fraudulent article by English physician Andrew Wakefield. Wakefield suggested a causal link between MMR vaccine and autism, but other researchers found no evidence. There were several flaws in his research as there was a low sample size of only 12 children and it relied on reports from parents. Many vaccines are given before signs of autism have even showed up which make people correlate the two together when there is no connection at all. There have been immense amounts of different research to find evidence of vaccine causing autism, but every research concludes in the same result that there is no correlation or evidence of vaccine causing autism. Not only has there been many experiments proving there are no relations between the two, but the timeline of autism and vaccines do not align. Autism has been a diagnosis seen about 20 years before the vaccine for measles, rubella and mumps were introduced (which was the original vaccine that was supposedly linked to autism). Lastly, autism has been linked as a strong genetic component. It has been discovered that autism has a high heritability rate which suggests that autism is largely determined by someone's genes proving once again that vaccines are not linked to autism.
References used for inspiration: Taylor, L. E., Swerdfeger, A. L., & Eslick, G. D. (2014). Vaccines are not associated with autism: An evidence-based meta-analysis of case-control and cohort studies. Vaccine, 32(29), 3623-3629. PART B: 1. Whether or not vaccines should be mandatory has been a continuous controversial issue. Those who are for the individual rights would argue that two pros would be personal autonomy and respect for personal beliefs and values, while those who are against this would argue they need to get vaccinated for public health and obligations to society. To begin with the pro individual rights, personal autonomy is the most compelling argument in favour of the anti-vaxxers stance as it sustains personal autonomy. People have the right to make their own choices in regard to their own health, which mandatory vaccines would disregard that right. Some individuals perceive the choice of vaccination as a serious personal decision that they should make on their own without the influence or coercion from the government. The other argument in favour for the right to refuse vaccines for individual rights would be respect for personal beliefs and values. Some individuals may have certain beliefs or values which do not agree and conflict with the view of vaccination. Whether it be religious or even philosophical, they may believe that alternating to a natural immunity is greater than a vaccine. They expect to be able to keep their beliefs and not be forced to go against their own personal values. They should be able to decide what is appropriate from their own view and have that decision respected. An argument for the cons of the individual rights would be the serious implications for public health. One of the most effective ways to prevent diseases from spreading are vaccines. When a large portion of the population is vaccinated, it creates herd immunity which is the most ideal as it protects everyone, including those who are not vaccinated. However, if a large population denies to take the vaccines, it can lead to outbreaks and faster spreading of a disease that can put those who are vulnerable at significant risk. Another argument against the right to refuse vaccination is the obligations to society that individuals have to protect the health and wellbeing of others. Those who refuse to vaccinate put others at risk, especially those who cannot get vaccinated due to medical reasons. Individuals have a responsibility to contribute themselves to aid in improvement and advancement for the greater good. In conclusion, it is difficult to say which is in the right as there are several other pros and cons towards the topic of individual rights and it is a debate that is continuous. 3. The distribution of scarce medical resources is a complex ethical issue that requires much cautious consideration of varied factors. In my opinion. Doctors, nurses, and other health care providers should not depend on any non-medical criteria when making choices around who gets these resources. Choices should instead be based only on medical criteria, such as the
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
seriousness of the patient's condition and the probability of recovery. There are a few reasons why non-medical criteria should not be used within the distribution of scarce medical resources. Firstly, it is critical to guarantee that medical decisions are made exclusively based on clinical need, instead of other components such as popularity, wealth, or political power. All patients should be given the same opportunities to get life-saving treatments regardless of their background or position in society; every individual should have equal rights. Furthermore, it is biased and discriminatory to have non-medical criteria in medical decision-making. An example would be if doctors were permitted to consider a patient's age or race when choosing who should get scarce medical resources, this may result in unjustifiable treatment such as sexism and racism of certain people or groups. This would be extremely unethical and unacceptable. Thirdly, depending on non-medical criteria may weaken trust within the healthcare system. If patients accept that their access to medical resources is being decided by components other than medical need, they may end up doubtful of the healthcare system and less willing to look for treatment when they require it. This may have profound consequences for public health. Finally, it is imperative to keep in mind that healthcare providers have a obligation to act within the best interests of their patients. This implies making choices based solely on medical criteria which prioritize the patient's needs over other considerations. All personal beliefs must be put aside as healing and saving a patient is the only thing a health care professional should think of. In conclusion, whereas the distribution of scarce medical resources could be a difficult and sometimes overbearing task, depending on non-medical criteria is not the solution. Choices around who gets medical resources should be based exclusively on medical criteria, to guarantee that all patients are treated equally and fairly, and that healthcare providers act within the best interests of their patients. 4. I disagree that Canada should adopt a more tolerant and supportive view of alternative medicine, and that governments should willing to fund many of them. First, rather than scientific research, alternative medicine is highly based on anecdotal evidence. Although some alternative therapies may show results or have benefits, there is no proof of any effectiveness the many alternative treatments may give. Publicly funding alternative medicine would take away money from the evidence-based medications or medical practices that have been tested and proven to work. This can cause many issues as it could have a negative impact on the health of Canadians due to less effective resources. Second, alternative medicine practitioners and conventional medical professionals are not held to the same standards. Alternative medicine does not have formal training or certification whereas conventional medical professionals go through extensive training and are monitored. There is less regulation for the alternative medicine practitioners which means that there is a possibility of receiving unsafe or ineffective care to which then the public funds would be misused (Berman). Third, having public funding going towards alternative medicine could create an unequal healthcare system. If only some of the alternative medicine is funded, patients who cannot afford to pay for the others that are not funded are left without access to care. This would further deepen the issue of health costs as some individuals already have issues affording conventional medicine. Splitting the funding would make both alternative and conventional medicine have low fundings making those who are less fortunate struggle even more to gain health care. This would lead to an unfair situation where only those who have
money have access to medications and therapies. Lastly, it is given the impression that alternative medicine is natural and safe but that is not always true. If certain alternative medicines are being used instead of evidence-based treatments, it can lead to serious effects on an individual's health. If alternative medicine is publicly funded, it would persuade Canadians into thinking that the government agrees on the safeness and effectiveness of these therapies when it is not necessarily true. This could break public trust in the healthcare system and put patients at risk. In conclusion, public funding should not go towards alternative medicines even if they may offer some benefits. There is a lack of scientific evidence, inconsistent regulation, unequal access, and risk of harm which are all strong reasons as to why experts and the government would and should not fund alternative medicine in Canada. It is important to prioritize the practices that are evidence-based and proved to work as well as to fund areas of greatest need to ensure safety and health to all Canadians. References used: Berman, B. M., Singh, B. K., Lao, L., Langenberg, P., Li, H., Hadhazy, V., & Bareta, J. (1995). Physicians’ attitudes toward complementary or alternative medicine: a regional survey. The Journal of the American Board of Family Practice, 8(5), 361-366.