Week four Journal
docx
keyboard_arrow_up
School
Brightwood College *
*We aren’t endorsed by this school
Course
347N
Subject
Philosophy
Date
Feb 20, 2024
Type
docx
Pages
4
Uploaded by dellie680
1
Inferences and Fallacies Doris Bangura
Chamberlain University
PHIL347N-13661
Dr. Todd Buck
06/05/2023
2
Inferences and Fallacies Inferences
The terms "valid inference" and "warranted inference" refer to the same thing in both
their definitions and their conceptualizations: What exactly do we mean when we say, "valid
inference"? The statement "drawing a wrong inference from facts before presenting it as fact"
accurately describes the action of reaching a judgment that is not supported by the data. As
defined by Shwartz (2020), a "warranted inference" refers to an argument where the proposer
claims that the finding achieved is very probable or near to the truth, despite the fact that it might
be true or untrue. The process of drawing such an inference is called "warranting" the
conclusion. Because "to prove" is one of the definitions of deductive reasoning, it implies that
the concept of valid inference is likewise relatively close to that of deductive reasoning. As a
result, having a grasp of what constitutes a valid inference will be advantageous in a variety of
settings. If someone is exceptionally good at dancing, and another person watches them and
thinks, "Wow, he's just dancing like Michael Jackson!" then that person is dancing like Michael
Jackson.
An inductive argument serves the same aim that a justified inference does, which is to
increase the likelihood of reaching a certain conclusion. One will have a better understanding of
the many different kinds of inductive reasoning if they have a firm grip on the idea of justified
inference (Hayes & Heit, 2018). For instance, one may interpret a girl's angry knocking on the
door as an indication of her displeasure with the situation. Regardless of whether or not her anger
is warranted by the situation.
Fallacies
3
A valid argument will not include any typos or spelling mistakes. Only by logically
following from other true premises can an argument be considered convincing. When the
conclusion does not fit with the premises, yet the premises do, the argument is fallacious. There
are two distinct kinds of logical fallacy: those that use a proper form but apply it incorrectly and
those that use no form at all (Facione, Gittens & Facione, 2016). Given (A) and (B), then (A)
implies (B) is an example of a logical error induced by the failure to account for the
counterfactual. In this case, it is correct to write "If A then B, A, therefore, B," which affirms the
consequent (the statement "If A then B, B therefore A"). The fallacy of assuming that anything
present or missing in part must be present in the whole is at play here; the correct form is "If A
then B, Not B, Therefore Not A"; for example, "A can do all his work very best, however, cannot
carry out it with others." When someone argues that anything present or missing in the whole
must also be present in the parts, they are making the division fallacy, which is the reverse of the
composition fallacy.
Civic Responsibility
Participants will be equipped with listened explanations from both perspectives of the
topic by the conclusion of the session, giving them plenty to chew on as they develop their own
opinions. It's crucial to focus on issues that might have far-reaching consequences for the
community as a whole. Citizens owe themselves to themselves and their communities to be
informed about pressing topics like health care reform, which affects us all (Facione & Gittens,
2016).
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
- Access to all documents
- Unlimited textbook solutions
- 24/7 expert homework help
4
References
Facione, P. A., Gittens, C. A., & Facione, N. C. (2016). Cultivating a critical thinking mindset.
Academia. Edu. Weekly Digest
,
28
.
Shwartz, V. (2021). Learning high-precision lexical inferences. Künstliche Intelligenz
.
Kane, M. T. (2021). Articulating a validity argument. In
The Routledge Handbook of language testing
(pp. 32-47). Routledge.
Hayes, B. K., & Heit, E. (2018). Inductive reasoning 2.0.
Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science
,
9
(3), e1459.
Facione, P. A., & Gittens, C. A. (2016).
Think critically
(3rd ed.). Pearson.