Houston-YaKh-Neg-4---Wake-Round-7 (1)

docx

School

Harrison College *

*We aren’t endorsed by this school

Course

2014

Subject

Law

Date

Nov 24, 2024

Type

docx

Pages

46

Uploaded by SargentRose8701

Report
1NC
1NC---OFF
FW---1NC---OFF First is framework : Our interpretation is that the AFF must defend the consequences of the hypothetical implementation of a topica l plan. ‘United States’ means the federal government, not private entities. Ikuta ’10 [Sandra; December 8; Circuit Judge for the United States Court of Appeals in the Ninth Circuit; Ninth Circuit, “Transwestern Pipeline Company, LLC v. 3.42 acres of permanent easement located in Maricopa County et al,” Lexis] We disagree with the last step of Agua Fria's analysis. When determining statutory meaning, we look first to the plain meaning of the text. Paul Revere Ins. Grp. v. United States, 500 F.3d 957, 962 (9th Cir. 2007). "[U]nless otherwise defined, words will be interpreted as taking their ordinary, contemporary, common meaning." Perrin v. United States, 444 U.S. 37, 42, 100 S. Ct. 311, 62 L. Ed. 2d 199 (1979). "When determining the plain meaning of language, we may consult dictionary definitions." Af-Cap Inc. v. Chevron Overseas (Congo) Ltd., 475 F.3d 1080, 1088 (9th Cir. 2007). Taking its ordinary , common meaning, the term " U nited S tates" means our nation , located primarily in North America, which acts through our federal form of government. The dictionary definition s are consistent with this common understanding . See, e.g., 19 Oxford English Dictionary 79-80 (J.A. Simpson & E.S.C. Weiner eds., 2d ed. 1989) (definition 1b: "The Republic of North America"); Black's Law Dictionary 1675 (9th ed. 2009) ("A federal republic . . . made up of 48 coterminous states, plus the state of Alaska and the District of Columbia in North America, plus the state of Hawaii in the Pacific."). 3 The Act does not define the term "United States" and does not indicate that we are to read the special definition of "Federal agency" from § 4601(1) into the term "United States." Accordingly, we decline to do so, and adhere instead to the common understanding of the term "United States." Given our interp retation of the term, the landowner's right to costs and fees is triggered only when the fed eral government abandons a condemnation proceeding, not when a private entity such as Transwestern does so, even if that private entity is exercising federally granted condemnation power . 4 Agua Fria contends that Tennessee Gas Pipeline Co. v. 104 Acres of Land, 828 F.Supp. 123 (D.R.I.1993), aff'd in part and vacated in part on other grounds, 32 F.3d 632 (1st Cir.1994), supports its contention that the term “United States” includes Transwestern for purposes of § 4654(a)(2). We disagree. In Tennessee Gas, a private gas company, acting under FERC's authority to acquire property for a pipeline, dismissed a condemnation proceedings it had brought against a landowner after FERC approved a change in the pipeline's route. Id. at 124–25. The district court held that, under these circumstances, it would deem FERC to have abandoned the proceedings for purposes of § 4654(a)(2). Id. at 128. The court therefore concluded that the landowner was entitled to litigation costs and fees under § 4654(a)(2) “whether or not Tennessee Gas is an entity within the term ‘United States' as used in the statute.” Id. In other words, Tennessee Gas avoided the very point Agua Fria claims it supports.5 5 “If the plain meaning of the statute is unambiguous, that meaning is controlling and we need not examine legislative history as an aid to interpretation unless the legislative history clearly indicates that Congress meant something other than what it said.” Greenwood v. CompuCredit Corp., 615 F.3d 1204, 1207 (9th Cir.2010) (quoting Carson Harbor Vill., Ltd. v. Unocal Corp., 270 F.3d 863, 877 (9th Cir.2001) (en banc)) (internal quotation marks omitted). Agua Fria has not pointed to any legislative history that contradicts the plain language of the statute. Rather, the House Report on which Agua Fria relies indicates that § 4654(a) was intended to reimburse property owners for fees and costs incurred “where (1) the court determines that a condemnation was unauthorized, [or] (2) the government abandons a condemnation.” H.R.Rep. No. 91–1656, 91st Cong.2d Sess., reprinted in 1970 U.S.C.C.A.N. 5850, 5874–75 (emphasis added). This interpretation is consistent with the plain language of the statute and does not suggest that Congress intended to make fees and costs available when a private party abandons a proceeding. Further, Congress made no changes to the term “United States” in § 4654(a)(2) when it changed the definition of “Federal agency” to include private persons. See Uniform Relocation Act Amendments of 1987, Pub.L. No. 100–17, § 402, 101 Stat. 132, 246. Had Congress wished to include private persons in the meaning of the term “United States,” it clearly knew how to do so. See Landgraf v. USI Film Prods., 511 U.S. 244, 255–56, 114 S.Ct. 1483, 128 L.Ed.2d 229 (1994). Because we adhere to the plain meaning of the term “ U nited S tates” in § 4654(a)(2), and that term does not include private entities , we affirm the district *1272 court's denial of Agua Fria's motion for litigation costs and fees.6 “Restrict” prohibits usage DeRosa & Nicolas 19 [Mary B. DeRosa & Ashley Nicolas, Mary B. DeRosa is a Professor from Practice at Georgetown Law, where she focuses on national security law. Previously, DeRosa served as deputy assistant and deputy counsel to the president and National Security Council legal adviser in the Obama administration. She has also served at the U.S. Mission to the United Nations as alternate representative of the United States to the 66th Session of the UN General Assembly, an ambassador-level position. Before the Obama administration, DeRosa was chief counsel for national security for the Senate Judiciary Committee, working for the chairman, Senator Patrick Leahy; senior fellow for technology and public policy at the Center for Strategic and International Studies; special assistant to the president and National Security Council legal adviser, and earlier deputy legal adviser, during the Clinton administration; and special counsel to the general counsel at the U.S. Department of Defense. Earlier in her career, DeRosa was a lawyer at the Arnold & Porter law firm and a law clerk to the Honorable Richard Cardamone, United States Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit. Ashley Nicolas is a 2019 Graduate of Georgetown University Law Center. At
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
GULC, Nicolas was a Global Law Scholar, president of the GULC Military Law Society, and student editor-in-chief of the Journal of National Security Law and Policy. Prior to law school, she served as a U.S. Army military intelligence officer. Her assignments included a deployment to Afghanistan with 4-2 Stryker Brigade Combat Team as an intelligence officer and female engagement team leader. After the Army, Nicolas taught secondary mathematics and computer science in San Jose, CA as a Teach for America corps member. She is an alumnus of the United States Military Academy, holding a BS in Sociology, and Loyola Marymount University, holding a M.Ed in Urban Education. Her work has been published in Foreign Policy’s Best Defense Blog, The Washington Post, The New York Times, and The Georgetown Law Journal Online. She is a 2016 Pat Tillman Foundation scholar and a 2018 Women in Defense HORIZONS scholar. “The President and Nuclear Weapons: Authorities, Limits, and Process,” 12-2019. https://media.nti.org/documents/The_President_and_Nuclear_Weapons_Authorities_Limits_and_Process.pdf] //schnit The U.S. Constitution’s division of war powers between the executive and legislative branches is notoriously murky. Few areas of law are more debated and less settled. The Constitution confers significant authority on each branch, but the exact scope of those authorities and the ways in which they interact remain controversial. Congressional authority might act in two principal ways to restrict a president’s decision to use nuclear weapons : (1) if the president is required to seek congressional authorization before use, and (2) if a statute prohibits or limits certain uses of those weapons . Nuclear forces consist of nuclear warheads and their delivery systems Congressional Budget Office 23 [Congressional Budget Office, Since 1975, CBO has produced independent analyses of budgetary and economic issues to support the Congressional budget process. Each year, the agency’s economists and budget analysts produce dozens of reports and hundreds of cost estimates for proposed legislation. “Projected Costs of U.S. Nuclear Forces, 2023 to 2032,” 6-2023. https://www.cbo.gov/publication/59365] //schnit U.S. nuclear forces consist of submarines that launch ballistic missiles (SSBNs), land-based intercontinental ballistic missiles ( ICBMs ), long-range bomber aircraft, shorter-range tactical aircraft carrying bombs , and the nuclear warheads that those delivery systems carry. Prefer it: Navigating complexity ---Abdicating the resolutional stasis sanctions picking any starting point for debate which incentivizes a retreat from controversy and eliminates the benefit of preround research . Only a common and stable point of engagement can ensure effective clash through critical thinking , reflexivity , and argument refinement , which is linear. Poscher 16 [Ralf Poscher, Diat the Institute for Staatswissenschaft and Philosophy of Law at the University of Freiburg “Why We Argue About the Law: An Agonistic Account of Legal Disagreement”, Metaphilosophy of Law, Tomasz Gizbert-Studnicki/Adam Dyrda/Pawel Banas (eds.), Hart Publishing. 2016.] Hegel’s dialectical thinking powerfully exploits the idea of negation . It is a central feature of spirit and consciousness that they have the power to negate. The spirit “is this power only by looking the negative in the face and tarrying with it. This […] is the magical power that converts it into being.”102 The tarrying with the negative is part of what Hegel calls the “labour of the negative ”103. In a loose reference to this Hegelian notion Gerald Postema points to yet another feature of disagreements as a necessary ingredient of the process of practical reasoning. Only if our reasoning is exposed to contrary arguments can we test its merits. We must go through the “labor of the negative” to have trust in our deliberative processes. 104 This also holds where we seem to be in agreement. Agreement without exposure to disagreement can be deceptive in various ways. The first phenomenon Postema draws attention to is the group polarization effect. When a group of like minded people deliberates an issue, informational and reputational cascades produce more extreme views in the process of their deliberations .105 The polarization and biases that are well documented for
such groups106 can be countered at least in some settings by the inclusion of dissenting voices. In these scenarios, disagreement can be a cure for dysfunctional deliberative polarization and biases .107 A second deliberative dysfunction mitigated by disagreement is superficial agreement, which can even be manipulatively used in the sense of a “presumptuous ‘We’”108. Disagreement can help to police such distortions of deliberative processes by challenging superficial agreements. Disagreements may thus signal that a deliberative process is not contaminated with dysfunctional agreements stemming from polarization or superficiality. Protecting our discourse against such contaminations is valuable even if we do not come to terms. Each of the opposing positions will profit from the catharsis it received “by looking the negative in the face and tarrying with it”. These advantages of disagreement in collective deliberations are mirrored on the individual level. Even if the probability of reaching a consensus with our opponents is very low from the beginning, as might be the case in deeply entrenched conflicts, entering into an exchange of arguments can still serve to test and improve our position . We have to do the “labor of the negative” for ourselves . Even if we cannot come up with a line of argument that coheres well with everybody else’s beliefs , attitudes and dispositions, we can still come up with a line of argument that achieves this goal for our own personal beliefs , attitudes and dispositions. To provide ourselves with the most coherent system of our own beliefs, attitudes and dispositions is – at least in important issues – an aspect of personal integrity – to borrow one of Dworkin’s favorite expressions for a less aspirational idea. In hard cases we must – in some way – lay out the argument for ourselves to figure out what we believe to be the right answer. We might not know what we believe ourselves in questions of abortion, the death penalty, torture, and stem cell research, until we have developed a line of argument against the background of our subjective beliefs, attitudes and dispositions . In these cases it might be rational to discuss the issue with someone unlikely to share some of our more fundamental convictions or who opposes the view towards which we lean. This might even be the most helpful way of corroborating a view, because we know that our adversary is much more motivated to find a potential flaw in our argument than someone with whom we know we are in agreement. It might be more helpful to discuss a liberal position with Scalia than with Breyer if we want to make sure that we have not overlooked some counter argument to our case. It would be too narrow an understanding of our practice of legal disagreement and argumentation if we restricted its purpose to persuading an adversary in the case at hand and inferred from this narrow understanding the irrationality of argumentation in hard cases, in which we know beforehand that we will not be able to persuade. Rational argumentation is a much more complex practice in a more complex social framework. Argumentation with an adversary can have purposes beyond persuading him : to test one’s own convictions , to engage our opponent in inferential commitments and to persuade third parties are only some of these ; to rally our troops or express our convictions might be others. To make our peace with Kant we could say that “there must be a hope of coming to terms” with someone though not necessarily with our opponent, but maybe only a third party or even just ourselves and not necessarily only on the issue at hand, but maybe through inferential commitments in a different arena. f) The Advantage Over Non Argumentative Alternatives It goes without saying that in real world legal disagreements, all of the reasons listed above usually play in concert and will typically hold true to different degrees relative to different participants in the debate: There will be some participants for whom our hope of coming to terms might still be justified and others for whom only some of the other reasons hold and some for whom it is a mixture of all of the reasons in shifting degrees as our disagreements evolve. It is also apparent that, with the exception of the first reason, the rationality of our disagreements is of a secondary nature. The rational does not lie in the discovery of a single right answer to the topic of debate, since in hard cases there are no single right answers . Instead, our disagreements are instrumental to rationales which lie beyond the topic at hand, like the exploration of our communalities or of our inferential commitments. Since these reasons are of this secondary nature, they must stand up to alternative ways of settling irreconcilable disagreements that have other secondary reasons in their favor – like swiftness of decision making or using fewer resources. Why does our legal practice require lengthy arguments and discursive efforts even in appellate or supreme court cases of irreconcilable legal disagreements? The closure has to come by some non argumentative mean and courts have always relied on them. For the medieval courts of the Germanic tradition it is bequeathed that judges had to fight it out literally if
they disagreed on a question of law – though the king allowed them to pick surrogate fighters.109 It is understandable that the process of civilization has led us to non violent non argumentative means to determine the law . But what was wrong with District Judge Currin of Umatilla County in Oregon, who – in his late days – decided inconclusive traffic violations by publicly flipping a coin?110 If we are counting heads at the end of our lengthy argumentative proceedings anyway, why not decide hard cases by gut voting at the outset and spare everybody the cost of developing elaborate arguments on questions, where there is not fact of the matter to be discovered? The United States should disarm its nuclear arsenal---it’s defers to the hibakusha Murakami 23 [Sakura Murakami; reporter for Reuters; 05-17-2023; "At Hiroshima G7, bomb survivors grapple with a disarmament dream deferred"; Reuters; https://www.reuters.com/world/asia- pacific/hiroshima-g7-bomb-survivors-grapple-with-disarmament-dream-deferred-2023-05-16/]//sheff The last time a U.S. president visited Hiroshima , atomic bomb survivor Shigeaki Mori was filled with hope for a future without nuc lear weapon s . Seven years later, he's more sceptical. As leaders of the Group of Seven (G7) nations gather in the Japanese city this week for a summit, Prime Minister Fumio Kishida wants a pledge on nuclear disarmament. Kishida, who represents Hiroshima, said he chose it for the summit to focus attention on nuclear weapons. But the venue has also highlighted a significant shift in global security since 2016, when Barack Obama became the first incumbent U.S. president to visit. For the West, Russia's Ukraine invasion has emphasised the importance of nuclear deterrence. Moscow has said it is ready to use its nuclear arsenal to defend its "territorial integrity" if necessary. Many of Japan's "hibakusha" - atomic bomb victims whose average age is 85 - worry the summit may be a final chance to call for disarm ament. They fear Hiroshima's legacy - its importance as the first city to be flattened by a nuc lear weapon - may be reduced to a historical artefact rather than a call for change . " I want to see the leaders commit to getting rid of nuc lear weapon s ," Mori, 86 , said in an interview. " I also know it's very hard to get them to go that far ."
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
Ballot---1NC---OFF Presenting the 1AC’s value as dependent on the recognition of the critic reduces the revolutionary nature of the act—fails to produce meaningful change and draws them into the oppressive gaze of the academy. Vote negative to refuse the affirmative’s call for the ballot Phillips 99 – Dr. Kendall R. Phillips, Professor of Communication at Central Missouri State University, PhD in Speech Communication from Pennsylvania State University, MA in Speech Communication from Central Missouri State University, BS in Psychology and Sociology from Southwest Baptist University, “Rhetoric, Resistance, and Criticism: A Response to Sloop and Ono”, Philosophy & Rhetoric, Volume 32, Number 1, p. 96-101 My concern with this movement centers around an issue that Sloop and Ono seem to take as a given, namely, the role of the critic . On one hand, calling for the systematic investigation of existing marginalized discourses is a natural extension both of critical rhetoric (see McKerrow 1989, 1991) and of the general ideological turn in criticism (see Wander 1983). On the other hand, the ease of transition from criticism in the service of resistance to criticism of resistance may obscure the need to address some fundamental issues regarding the general function of rhetorical criticism in an uncertain and contentious world . Beyond licensing the critic to engage in political struggle , Sloop and Ono advocate the pursuit of covert resistant discourses. Such a move not only stretches our understanding of rhetoric and criticism, but also alters significantly the relationship between critic and out- law. Critical interrogation of dominant discursive practices in the service of political/cultural reform is supplanted in favor of positioning covert out- law communities as objects of investigation . Invited to seek out subversive discourses, the critic is positioned as the active agent of change and the out-law discourse becomes merely instrumental . Rather than academic criticism acting in service of everyday acts of resistance, everyday acts of resistance are put into the service of academic criticism. Rhetorical resistance That we are "caught within conflicting logics of justice that are culturally struggled over" (Sloop and Ono 1997, 50) and that rhetoric is employed in these struggles seems an uncontroversial statement. Despite the theoretical miasma surrounding judgment, Sloop and Ono accurately note, the material process of rendering judgments (and of disputing the logics of litigation) continues in the world of actually practiced discourse. In the materially contested world, rhetoric is utilized both by those seeking to secure the grounds of dominant judgment and by those seeking to undermine or supplant dominant cultural logics with some out-law notion of justice. The distinction between these two cultural groups, "in-law" and out- law, however, deserves some consideration prior to any discussion of the role of the critic as implied in the out-law discourse project. The discourse of the dominant or those within the bounds of superordinate logics of litigation is reminiscent of Michel De Certeau's (1984) strategic discourse. For De Certeau, strategies are utilized by those who have authority by virtue of their proper position. Strategies exploit the institutionally guaranteed background consensus by which power relations (and litigations) are maintained and advanced. In contrast, tactics are utilized by those having no proper place of authority within the discursive economy who must seek opportunities whereby the discourse of the dominant might be undermined and contested. To extend Sloop and Ono's definition, out-law discourses are those that can (and, by their analysis, do) take advantage of situations (e.g., race riots) to disrupt the regularity of dominant cultural groups. The ongoing struggle between strategically instituted cultural dominants and the "out-law always lurk[ing] in the distance" (66) is acknowledged, even celebrated, by Sloop and Ono. What their acknowledgment fails to provide, however, is a clear need for critical intervention. Indeed, quite the reverse is presented: It is the critic (particularly the left-leaning critic) who needs out-law discourse. While the struggles over justice, equality, and freedom have gone on, the left-leaning critics are those who have theoretically excluded themselves from the disputes. The study of out-law dis- courses, then, provides a means to reinvigorate the intellectual and re-institute (academic) leftist thinking into popular political struggles (53-54). Thus, Sloop and Ono's project incorporates three types of rhetoric: the rhetoric of the in-law, presumably the traditional object of critical attention; the rhetoric of the out-law, the study of which may transform our understanding of judgment as well as reinvigorate leftist democratic critiques; and the rhetoric of the critics who, having lost their political po- tency, can exploit the discourse of the out-law to promote ideological struggles. It is to this critical rhetoric that I now turn. Resistance criticism Sloop and Ono (1997) clearly state the relationship they envision between the rhetorical critic and out-law discourse: "Ultimately, we will argue that the role of critical rhetoricians is to produce 'materialist conceptions of judgment,' using out-law judgments to disrupt dominant logics of judgment" (54; emphasis added). Here the critic seeks out vernacular discourse (60), focuses on the methods and values embodied in these communities (62), listens to and evaluates the out-law community (62-63), and chooses appropriate discourses for the purpose of disrupting dominant practices (63). Essentially, it is the critic who seeks out marginalized discourses and returns them to the center for the purpose of provoking dominant cultural groups (63). Despite acknowledging the efficacy of out-law discourses, Sloop and Ono assume that the critiques generated and presented by the out-law community have only minimal effect. The irony, and indeed arrogance, of this assumption is evident when they claim: "There are cases, however, when, without the prompting of academic critics, out-law discourses serve local purposes at times and at others resonate within dominant discourses, disrupting sedimented ways of thinking, transforming dominant forms of judgment" (60; emphasis added). Sloop and Ono seem to suggest that such locally generated critiques are the exception, whereas the political efficacy of the academic critic is the rule. This seems an odd claim, given that the justification for their out-law discourse project is the lack of politically viable academic critique and the perceived potency of out-law conceptions of judgment. Their suggestion that out-law
communities are in need of the academic critic contradicts not only the already disruptive nature of existing out-law discourses (the grounds for using out-law discourse), but also the impotence of contemporary critical discourse (the warrant for studying out-law discourse). By this I do not mean that the critiques and theories generated by academically instituted intellectuals have not been incorporated into subversive discourses. Just as out-law discourses inevitably mount critiques of dominant logics, so, too, the perspectives on rhetoric and criticism generated by academics are used in resistance movements. Feminist critiques of patriarchy, queer theories of homophobia, postcolonial interrogations of race have found their way into the service of resistant groups. The key distinction I wish to make is that the existence of criticism (academic or self-generated) in resistance does not necessitate Sloop and Ono's move to a criticism of resistance. What Sloop and Ono fail to offer is an adequate argument for " taking public speaking out of the streets and studying it in the classroom , for treating it less as an expression of protest " (Wander 1983, 3) and more as an object for analysis and reproduction within the political economy of the academy . Philip Wander made a similar charge against Herbert Wicheln's early critical project, and this concern should remain at the forefront of any discussion aimed at expanding the scope and function of criticism. Sloop and Ono offer numerous directives for the critic without addressing whether the critic should be examining out-law discourses in the first place . While it is too early to suggest any definitive answer to the question of criticism of resistance, some preliminary arguments as to why critics should not pursue out-law discourses can be offered: (1) Hidden out-law discourses may have good reasons to stay hidden . Sloop and Ono specifically instruct us that "the logic of the out-law must constantly be searched for, brought forth" (66) and used to disrupt dominant practices. But are we to believe that all out-law discourses are prepared to mount such a challenge to the dominant cultural logic? Or, indeed, that the members of out- law communities are prepared to be brought into the arena of public surveillance in the service of reconstituting logics of litigation? It seems highly unlikely that all divergent cultural groups have developed equally, or that all members of these groups share Sloop and Ono's "imperial impulse" (51) to promote their conceptions and practices of justice. (2) Academic critical discourse is not transparent. Here I allude to the overall problem of translation (see Foucault 1994; Lyotard 1988; Lyotard and Thebaud 1985; Zabus 1995) as an extension of the previous concern. Critical discourse cannot become the medium of commensurability for divergent language games. Are we to believe that the "use" of out-law dis- course by critics to disrupt dominant practices can fail to do violence to these diverse/divergent logics? Are out-law discourses merely tools to be exploited and discarded in the pursuit of returning leftist academic dis- course to the center? (3) Perhaps the academic translation of out-law discourse could be true to the internal logic of the out-law community. And, perhaps the re-presentation of out-law logic within the academic community will bestow a degree of legitimacy on the out-law community. Nonetheless , the effect of legitimizing out-law discourse is unknown and potentially destructive . In an effort to siphon the political energy of out-law discourse into academic practice, we may ultimately destroy the dissatisfaction that serves as a cathexis for these out-law discourses . It seems possible that academic recognition might take the place of struggle for material opportunities (see Fraser 1997). But, will academic legitimation create any material changes in the conditions of out-law communities? I mean to suggest, not that it is better to allow the out-law community to suffer for its cause, but rather that incorporating the struggle into an (admittedly) impotent academic critique does not offer a prima facie alternative. (4) Criticism of resistance denies the practical and theoretical importance of opportunity. Returning to De Certeau's notion of tactics, the crucial element of these discursive moves is their use of opportunity to disrupt the proper authority of the dominant. The kairos of intervention provides the key to undermining "in-law" discourses. But when is the "right moment in time" for the academic reproduction of out-law discourse? Mapping the points of resistance (ala Foucault and Biesecker) entails interrogating "in-law" discourses for their incongruities and contradictions, not turning the academic gaze upon those communities waiting for an opportunity. Out-laws do not lurk in the forefront (66), hoping to be exposed by academic critics; they wait for the right moment for their disruption. Rhetoricians can provide rhetorical instructions for seeking opportunities and for exploiting these opportunities (literally making the culturally weaker argument the stronger), but this does not justify interrogating (intervening in) the cultural logics of the marginalized. The concerns raised here are not designed to dismiss Sloop and Ono's provocative essay. The divergent critical logic they outline deserves careful consideration within the critical community, and it is my hope that the concerns I raise may help to further problematize the relationship between resistance and rhetorical criticism. Rhetorical criticism As I have suggested, my purpose is to use the provocative nature of Sloop and Ono's project to extend disputes regarding the ends of rhetorical criticism. Diverging perspectives on the ends of criticism have been categorized by Barbara Warnick (1992) as falling along four general lines: artist, analyst, audience, and advocate. Leah Ceccarelli (1997) discerns similar categories around the aesthetic, epistemic, and political ends of rhetorical criticism. The out-law discourse project presents clear ties to the notion of critic as advocate. For Sloop and Ono, the critic is an interested party , discerning (and at times disputing) the underlying values and forces contained within a discourse. Additionally, however, the out-law discourse critic is an analyst focusing on the hidden , aberrant texts of the out-law and "rendering] an incoherent or esoteric text comprehensible" (Warnick 1992, 233). Now, I am not suggesting that a critic must serve only one function or that the roles of advocate and analyst are mutually exclusive; rather, these entanglings of power (political ends) and knowledge (epistemic ends) are inevitable . My concern is that we not neglect the complexity of these entanglements. Turning covert out-law discourses into objects of our analyses runs the risk of subjecting them both to
the gaze of the dominant and to the power relations of the academy . As the works of Michel Foucault (especially 1979, 1980) aptly illustrate, practices presented as extending such noble goals as emancipation and humanity may endow institutions of confinement and objectification. Any justification for studying out-law dis- course because doing so may extend our political usefulness in the pursuit of emancipatory goals must not obscure the already existing power relations authorizing such studies. Our attempts to extend our domains of knowledge and expertise (authority) must not be pursued unreflexively.
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
Ishiro Honda---1NC---OFF We affirm the entirety of the aff except for their citation of ishiro honda He administrated comfort women camps. He is a WAR CRIMINAL Scherschel 20, [Brian Scherschel Brian is the creator, editor, director, and host at Kaijuvision Radio. He loves classic and foreign films. He’s also a violinist. He graduated with honors from Wabash College where he received my B.A. in Political Science, concentrating in International Relations. He then received his Master’s of Public Administration from the School of Public and Environmental Affairs at Indiana University-Bloomington, concentrating in Comparative Politics and International Affairs. Some of his favorite subjects in his studies include NATO, the European Union, European history, globalization, urban American history, non-democratic regimes, and national and international security concerns (high politics). “Episode 57: Ishiro Honda and Crimes Against Humanity” August 24, 2020, http://www.kaijuvision.com/2020/08/24/episode-57-ishiro-honda-and-crimes-against-humanity/] First I’ll give you some background. In episode 4 of the show, I covered the issue of the Tokyo War Crimes Tribunal. I utilized a few sources plus what I already knew and thought about regarding the subject. I’ve never shied away from a subject because it was too difficult for me to read about and process. But I’ll preface what I say with this: It’s not my place to forgive Ishiro Honda for what he did under the command of the Imperial Japanese Army . It also isn’t your place to forgive him . The only ones who can forgive him are the women (and men ) who were put in the camps . And it isn’t Godzilla fandom experts’ place to downplay the significance of that chapter of his life . I can only give you my analysis of what I’ve learned and thought about. Honda was in a command position at a comfort women camp during World War II. He administered actions there . He would have participated in “acquiring” women for the camp , also known as abducting , or kidnapping, and forcing them into sexual slavery . Human trafficking is another way to put this . These actions classify him as a class C war criminal , for crimes against humanity. He was not arrested, charged, or punished after the war was over.
Image---1NC---OFF Affirm the entirety of the 1AC except their insertion of the images The AFF’s illustrations spectacularize the violence of imperialism which sanitizes violence and siphons ability to embrace it. Their evidence. 1AC Gatdula 23 , Assistant Professor @ University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill. (Anna Beatrice, “Spectacles of a Nuclear Empire: Opera and Film in the American Atomic Age, 1945-2018,” June 2023, University of Chicago, luna) Delivering an address at the celebratory unveiling, Professor Harold Haydon remarked: “As this bronze monument remembers an event and commemorates an achievement, it has something unique to say about the spiritual meaning of the achievement, for it is the special power of art to convey feeling and stir profound emotion, to touch us in ways that are beyond the reach of reason [emphasis mine].”27 The statue marked the very place where, several feet below ground, Fermi had successfully created the first nuclear chain reaction. Through the ritualistic acts of remembering and commemorating, the University staked its claim within US nuclear empire. Only five years beforehand (1962), US nuclear supremacy was at its most challenged, but its deterrence, with the U.S.S.R. during the Cuban Missile Crisis, reaffirmed its control over global order and geopolitical conflict. If spectacle is the superstructure, then nuclear empire is the base, this age’s “ mode of production .” I use the designation “nuclear empire” to name the period of US supremacy in the post-1945 world order. The nuclear empire spans the years (1946–1991), known as the years of the Cold War, but I extend the periodization to our present day. One could say “nuclear empire” names US supremacy in the Cold War’s long durée , which other historians have termed the “The Long Cold War.”28 It not only hearkens to US political history but also to the structural function of the nation-state during this time. In this I deviate from musicological studies of Cold War Music. The American Musicological Society’s Cold War Study Group, for example, “investigates the music composed during the decades after World War II, and specifically the relationship between new music and the continuing global opposition between the United States and the U.S.S.R..”29 Though the period of my project correlates with that of the disciplinary boundaries taken up by Cold War studies, I am not investigating historical changes in musical styles during this period. Indeed, the spectacle I have in mind exceeds generic confines. Hence my work means to describe how this spectacular excess is inherent to nuclear empire’s reification . Recent scholarship focusing on the literary tradition in the nuclear age centers the formal ways nuclear empire shapes cultural artefacts . Maria Anna Mariani’s monograph Italian Literature in the Nuclear Age: The Poetics of the Bystander poses a serious question about the role of Italy and its citizens as passive accomplices.30 She claims that authors like Italo Calvino and Elsa Morante test the generic limits of science fiction, creating works that are both politically engaged in content and postmodern in form.31 She sees Calvino’s work as a formalist intervention dealing with the new space-time paradigm of the nuclear age. Her insights help enrich my own readings, especially with respect to opera where nuclear content began to take on a postmodern form now known as musical minimalism.32 Closer to the center of nuclear empire, Jessica Hurley’s work on the “ nuclear mundane articulates the ways that narratives of nuclear apocalypse obfuscate the everyday violence occurring at the environmental and infrastructural levels .33 I follow Hurley’s critical attention to the material ramifications of such narratives. In particular, her formulation of the “ nuclear mundane demands that we pay attention to the nuc lear problem as “ the slow violence of the atomic age.” “Like all slow violence,” Hurley writes, nuclear violence distributes its damage unevenly . Poor people, people of color, Indigenous people, queer people, and women receive the least benefit from the nuclear complex and are most exposed to its harm .”34 The study of empire calls attention to US geopolitical maneuvers post-1945.35 From its annexation of the Bikini Atoll in the Pacific to the Marshall Plan across the Atlantic, the United States used its military power for imperial occupation . Moreover, the US deployed imperial tactics within its own continental borders. The policies of eminent domain have been used to create sacrifice zones within the US for uranium mining and nuclear waste . Often these lands are under Native American sovereignty.36 Military power
ensures nuclear empire’s dominance and growth of capital . Empire is always in process and, by extension, is always narrativizing or reifying itself .37 Cultural responses —in my work, spectacular representations— have always played a central role in imperial expansion and help construct imperial subjects .38 As US historian Amy Kaplan argues, “ Foregrounding imperialism in the study of American cultures shows how putatively domestic conflicts are not simply contained at home but how they both emerge in response to international struggles and spill over national boundaries to be reenacted, challenged, or transformed .”39 How the US presents international struggle will reflect domestic tensions—externalized projections of internal conflict. The American public’s attachment to the nation is predicated on a global, relational extimacy.40 During the African American Civil Rights movement, leaders would name nuclear disarmament as a necessity for a truly anti-colonial liberation.41 From Martin Luther King, Jr., to Angela Y. Davis, these leaders would connect the Black freedom struggle to geopolitical issues, linking freedom, peace, and anti-colonialism in their activism. In a speech addressed to the Black Woman’s Forum, Angela Davis entreated the audience of her peers as follows: We can no longer afford to assume that peace is a white folks’ issue. How can we in good conscience separate ourselves from the fight for peace when nuclear bombs do not know how to engage in racial discrimination? And if it were at all conceivable that nuclear fallout could be programmed to kill some of us while sparing others, I can guarantee you that the warmakers in this country would see to it that Black people would be its first victims.42 A similar response from Reverend J. E. Elliott that followed President Truman’s 6 August 1945 announcement speaks to a pan-racial solidarity in the face of nuclear empire. He told his congregation, “I have seen the course of discrimination throughout the war and the fact that Japan is of a darker race is no excuse for resorting to such an atrocity.”43 In the historiography of nuclear empire, the histories of Black and Indigenous experiences have been articulated as separate spheres. Though mine is not a cultural history of those communities, it does bring together and center accounts of imperial harm. Nuclear empire sees one race that is reduced to a quest for supremacy in the arms race. As I retell historical narratives around these cultural responses, I want to keep these anti-imperial messages close at hand. The spectacle functions to obfuscate those violences of empire that are unspectacular . The atomic bomb will always incite fear of apocalypse and mass extinction, but the everyday infrastructures that maintain nuclear empire always already enact violence on bodies (human and nonhuman) through violences done to land, air, and water .44 If these stories of imperial harm to ordinary citizens are not explicitly on my page, they are central to my intent and commitment. The post-War United States was a time for reimagining US citizenship , requiring what Lauren Berlant described as “ the orchestration of fantasies about the promise of the state and the nation to cultivate and protect a consensually recognized ideal of the ‘ good life .’ ”45 The nuclear spectacle haunted and terrorized. In return for the state-backed security it promised, the American public was asked to love their country and to recognize certain stories , events, experiences, practices , and ways of life as related to the core of who they were, their public status, and their resemblance to other people .46 Given the near impossibility of containing atomic weapons and nuclear radiation, a rhetoric of containment made possible the propagandistic American narrative that undergirded its national identity .47 By 1984, Jacques Derrida was applying his deconstructionist method so as to articulate the problems of nuclear empire. According to Derrida, the problem that plagued nuclear empire, as evidenced by the geopolitical course of the Cold War, was that the bomb was “fabulously textual.”48 His argument boils down to the essential point that we talk about the bomb so that we may never use the bomb: that is the “missive” of Mutually Assured Destruction. The paradox of the nuclear problem is that quantity stands in a negative relation to utility, hence quantity represents an inherent perversion of the capitalist understanding of use-value: more nuclear weapons mean less use of weapons. This perverse use-value is sustained by the demonstration, the spectacle, which insists that the bomb could be useful. It’s that paradox that leads Derrida to argue that the bomb is “fabulously textual” and thus “a speculation, even a fabulous specularization.”49 On this account, the spectacular displays of post-nuclear annihilation, mushroom clouds, and radiation’s effects naturalize the spectators’ understanding and acceptance of the nuclear problem. Spectators are left to speculate about when the spectacle might become “the real thing.” Aesthetic Strategy and the Ideology of Nuclear Empire Spectacle is inherent to nuclear empire’s use of the atomic bomb. In a declassified memo from the US military Target Committee, the leaders outlined the psychological factors in choosing certain Japanese targets. Under article “E: The Psychological Factors in Target Selection” the memo states:
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
It was agreed that psychological factors in the target selection were of great importance. Two aspects of this are (1) obtaining the greatest psychological effect against Japan and (2) making the initial use sufficiently spectacular for the importance of the weapon to be internationally recognized when publicity on it is released.50 I claim that the spectacle constitutes the aesthetic strategy used to produce and circulate nuclear empire’s hegemonic ideology . The atomic bomb proved to be an epistemic shift , part of a culture in which empire was sublimated through various media . Cultural critic Rey Chow writes , “ It was probably no accident that the United States chose as its laboratory , its site of experimentation , a civilian rather than military space, since the former, with a much higher population density, was far more susceptible to demonstrating the upper ranges of the bomb’s spectacular potential .”51 It was not simply that hard science was replaced by a visual device, but that “the dropping of the bombs marked the pivot in the progress of science.”52 As an aesthetic strategy, the spectacle is one of many strategies in the arsenal of nuclear empire. The spectacle of the atomic bomb coheres a public , one that includes spectators, victims, and witnesses, all of whom can testify to the ongoing violence of nuclear technology . These violences are made a spectacle while at the same time paradoxically occurring on the level of the ordinary or mundane. A public made manifest by the nuclear problem is first built imaginatively. I propose spectacle as a cultural response to our nuclear age, and I follow in the methods of critical theorists in trying to understand how culture continues to shape and obfuscate political attachments . My work offers one perspective on the relation between spectacular mediation and historical meaning-making, exploring it through the media of opera and film. I make a distinction between aesthetic strategy and aesthetic category, particularly in relation to the sublime. Frances Ferguson’s essay on the nuclear sublime posits the atomic bomb as the most recent version of the sublime, quoting Edmund Burke, “We love the beautiful as what submits to us, we fear the sublime as what we must submit to.”53 According to Ferguson, the nuclear sublime becomes a useful lever in discussions of aesthetics because it helps “an individual identify himself, to attach himself to a consciousness of his own individuality.”54 The perception of the sublime adheres to the individual’s act of individual judgment: the sublime is enlisted in the search for a unique individual subjectivity, the sublime affirms individual identity at the expense of the notion of private ownership, and, finally, the virtue of the sublime is that it cannot be exchanged. You don’t want to witness another’s sublime; it encroaches on your individuality.55 I am not proposing here that the atomic bomb is inherently sublime. I want to make the distinction that the atomic bomb is spectacular, which, if it has anything to do with the sublime, is a bad form of it, what we might call a bad sublimation. The term “nuclear sublime” implies that the nuclear exceeds understanding, but my own historical impulse is to insist that the atomic bomb has historical actors and victims from whom we can learn. Moreover, the spectacle implies the presence of the spectator and can bring together a collective of spectators. With a certain amount of razzle dazzle, the spectacle vies for control over affect and affected bodies , creating a space and time for spectators to relate to or contest the narratives presented. I insist on the spectacle as an aesthetic strategy that narrativizes and reifies nuclear empire because I want to consider the ways that spectacle as a form and an experience can not only be used to mystify spectators but be deployed strategically to critique nuclear empire , as happens in the operas I take up in this dissertation. At its core, “nuclear empire” calls attention to the epoch-changing technology of nuclear weapons science. The field of Science and Technology Studies has been instrumental to my thinking about the dialectical relation between technology and culture. Cultural figurations of nuclear technology represent historically specific reactions and interpretations. Anthropologist Joseph Masco articulates a central question of nuclear empire: “What kind of cultural work is performed in the act of making something ‘unthinkable’? How has the social regulation of the imagination —in this case, of nuclear war— been instrumental in American life since World War II?” 56 Masco makes a compelling inquiry into the intersections between nuclear technoscience, culture, and everyday life. Starting from the premise that “the invention of the atomic bomb transformed everyday life, catching individuals within a new articulation of the global and the local,” Masco proposes a new study of aesthetics that he formulates as technoaesthetics : “ the evaluative aesthetic categories embedded in the expert practices of weapons scientists. …are the non-classified everyday modes of interacting with nuclear technologies .”57 According to Masco, aestheticizing the bomb—literally the sensory experience of the bomb—was crucial to the development of the technology. Technoaesthetics were further imbricated in geopolitical matters , a history of the bomb he recounts in three parts: 1945–1962, above ground testing; 1963–1992, subterranean testing; and from 1995–2010, computer-generated model testing.58 Masco argues that the three different periods of testing offer three different technoaesthetic
modes of engagement. During above-ground testing, scientists could feel in their bodies the effects of ever-growing nuclear weapons technology and could thus apprehend the dangerous real-world consequences.59 The scientists aestheticized the bomb, apprehended the bomb through their bodily senses, and understood the bomb’s spectacular power through visual, sonic, and haptic senses as their bodies were shocked by the bomb’s light, sound, and heat . As bomb testing moved underground and then to the furthest removed technological mediation of computergenerated models, scientists could no longer feel the bomb, thus losing a sense of what the bomb might mean in the real world. Masco argues that their physical detachment from the bomb allowed scientists to fetishize the bomb : the further desensitized (or, de-aestheticized) the scientists became, the more they sublimated the bomb ultimately losing a sense of the real repercussions of their evermore powerful and dangerous weapon . As a formal principle, the aesthetic strategy of spectacle attempts to subsume its opposite— the “unspectacular.” The spectacular bomb is made through unspectacular infrastructures and experiments , like the giant graphite pile of CP-1. The dialectical impulse in play in this project follows the work of Masco and Hurley who study the everyday, “ordinary” violences of nuclear technology in US culture and literature. 60 I take up Jessica Schwartz’s proposal to examine the “ nuclear silences inherent in the structures of imperial domination . Schwartz’s ethnographic work and activism with and for the indigenous populations of the Marshallese Islands attest to an ongoing silencing a tool to maintain nuclear empire’s hegemonic control .61 I want to take this critical intervention further by holding silence , or the “ unspectacular ,” in the same space as spectacle to claim that both are aesthetic characteristics of ideological authority . My analysis of ideology focuses not only on spectators, then, but institutions and (intimate) publics . Following Terry Eagleton, I think of ideology as “that which makes the subject feel the world is not an inhospitable place.”62 Ideology is the larger belief system that legitimates the power of a dominant social group or class, and can become dominant through six ways: promotion, naturalization, universalization, denigration, exclusion, and mystification.63 The ideology that interests me is that of nuclear empire, the ideology that maintains the necessity for nuclear supremacy—this belief makes the subject (spectator or ordinary citizen) feel the world is a more hospitable place with the presence and proliferation of nuclear technology. It is an ideology mired in imperial action—conquest of lands and peoples—but also of technological exceptionalism. The United States is hardly a stranger to the ideology of exceptionalism.64 Throughout its history, the nation-state’s ideology permeated myths of the frontier. US historian Greg Grandin defines the frontier myth: “The concept of the frontier served as both diagnosis (to explain the power and wealth of the United States) and prescription (to recommend what policy makers should do to maintain and extend that power and wealth).”65 In our nuclear age, the frontier manifests in the Bikini Atoll for testing of the hydrogen bomb, toward the moon in a race against the Soviet Union, and at the quantum reaches of the atom. At the core of this expansionist drive is the ideology that upholds nuclear empire. The spectacle specifies—moreover, actualizes and materializes—the relation between aesthetics and ideology . In order to represent, reproduce, and circulate the beliefs of nuclear empire, the spectacle must be deployed as an aesthetic strategy. Again, as exemplified by the Target Committee memo, the spectacular nature of the bomb was a deliberate (aesthetic) strategy toward geopolitical ends. My work covers the long durée of the nuclear age, from the hot and cold fluctuations of the Cold War to a post-9/11 United States. While geopolitical contexts change over time, the spectacle as a means of narrating our nuclear age adapts to these historical developments. I hope that the historical critique will be one among many that analyze American narratives of exceptionalism. Ultimately, I claim that the ideological and aesthetic are distinct but interdependent spheres of influence, both necessary to establish and maintain the nuclear empire. American Opera in the Nuclear Age My work brings opera into the larger conversation about media spectacle. I claim that opera is an aesthetic medium unlike film and television that begs for a different kind of intersubjective relation than they do—one among story tellers, performers, and audience (read: spectators). It differs from electronic media in that many of the laboring forces are right in front of you, breathing the very same air that you breathe in the opera house, at least in live performance.
While many scholars have studied mass media in relation to histories of nuclear technology, no one has yet done so in ways that make opera central. 66 My work centers opera within a larger study of spectacle because of its intimate public, primarily in opera houses themselves.67 Following the work of Berlant, I use the term “ intimate public ” to denote a collective whose intimate lives or personal affects and feelings are constituted by their consumption of a common medium or their participation in a common mediascape .68 An intimate public is bound together by a structure of feeling , pace Williams, that defines forms and conventions as elements of “ social material process .”69 Individuals and ordinary citizens do not live in world views ” or “ideologies” but rather practice a variable relation between the meaning and value of their affective life and formal or systemic beliefs .70 They are in a constant flow between an internal and external drive toward living “the good enough life.” 71 What’s crucial about naming an intimate public as such is the critique entailed concerning the political (in)action of the collective . Berlant’s work on classic Hollywood cinema, for example, attends to “ the intimate public’s tendency to route its optimism toward affects and aesthetics as against the conventionally political .”72 It is enough to feel utopian without having utopia : In mass-mediated intimate publicity, the utopian and heterotopian are adapted to a scene of bargaining not with fulfillment (that would be politics ) but with sensually lived potentiality .”73 The operas I foreground do not argue outright for the deactivation of nuclear weapons and instead seem to say that being protected by the existence of US bombs and not being bombed oneself right now feels good enough. Their circulation of the photo of Gidra appropriates it . CX clarified ANYBODY gets to interpret the image Sandrine Boudana et al 17 , Tel Aviv University, Department of Communications, Faculty Member, “Reviving icons to death: when historic photographs become digital memes,” Media, Culture & Society 2017, Vol. 39(8) 1210–1230, https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/pdf/10.1177/0163443717690818 Despite the overall lack of agreement, three major traits consistently recur: (a) the recognition of these photos by a large public, (b) their repetition and recycling across media platforms, and (c) their broad social and moral significance , beyond the referential meaning of the originally reported event. In fact, these three features are mutually reinforcing: Circulation and replication facilitate public recognition of iconic photos , while the assumption that these photos will be recognized encourages their intertextual recycling . They are recognized and reproduced because they are endowed with extensive social and moral meaning , but the range and scope of their interpretations also expand as a consequence of their reuse in new contexts . For instance, examining the case of the 1989 ‘Tank Man’ image of the protester facing tanks in Tiananmen Square, Lee et al. (2011) show how ‘the media have extracted and abstracted Tiananmen from its original context to symbolize complex, contradictory, and generalized layers of meanings’ about China (p. 336). More specifically, while for the American press Tiananmen initially symbolized Communist dictatorship, it became the symbol of China’s violation of human rights later in the 1990s, and its significance faded away in the 2000s, although ‘it remained as part of United States’ ritualistic memory of China’s repression that invokes the moral bottom line of US foreign policy’ (p. 335). By granting the original event broader moral and emotional meaning, these photos can also give birth to new events. ‘Accidental Napalm’ is not merely an illustration of one particular accident among the many tragic incidents of the Vietnam War: its publication became an event in its own right, contributing to a series of other events, including protests against that war, but also against other wars, as well as other suffering and injustice (Hariman and Lucaites, 2007; for a nuanced account, see Westwell, 2011). These emphases on iconic recycling as a dynamic, generative force have led to uses of the term ‘icon’ beyond its primary association with visual media.2 Bennett and Lawrence (1995), for example, use the term ‘news icons’ to describe ‘images’ – both overtly visual and also verbal ‘word- pictures’ – that emerge ‘when an ongoing news story is crystalized into a dramatic event’ (p. 23). Like iconic photographs, news icons are recycled and inserted into other news narratives, as they ‘not only dominate the events within which they originate but are used by journalists to evoke larger cultural themes, symbolizing values, contradictions, or changes that have begun to surface in society’ (p. 23). More recently, Sonnevend (2016) has shown how the Western journalistic account of ‘the fall of the Berlin Wall’ is an almost myth-like condensation of a chaotic sequence of occurrences. Crucially, the ‘fall of the wall’ has since been turned into a ‘global iconic event’ through diverse aesthetic
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
practices of recycling – textual, visual, and even architectural; these have shaped accounts of subsequent separation walls and fences in other contexts. Such broadenings of the concept of the icon intersect with contemporary theorizations of ‘iconic power’ (Alexander et al., 2012) that connect aesthetic form and sociopolitical influence. Alexander (2010) defines icons as ‘symbolic condensations that root social meanings in material form, allowing the abstractions of cognition and morality to be subsumed, to be made invisible, by aesthetic shaping’ (p. 10). The materiality of icons converts abstract ideas into sensory experiences, enabling them to ‘concentrate and direct emotions’ and convey moral values in powerful ways (Hariman and Lucaites, 2007: 36). Alexander (2010) goes so far as to postulate an ‘iconic consciousness’ which ‘occurs when an aesthetically shaped materiality signifies social value’ (p. 11). Finally, the term ‘iconic’ suggests that iconic photographs are not only widely known and culturally resonant but also publicly sanctified. This idea, used conspicuously by Hariman and Lucaites, is greatly indebted to Christian traditions of venerating religious images, although it is also – as we elaborate below – connected to the institutional structures of modern journalism. The importance of sacredness finds a parallel in the idea that photography can be auratic, in Walter Benjamin’s (1980, 1992) sense, constituting a record of the unique spatiotemporal field of the depicted object. Iconic photographs are thus doubly sanctified, their public canonization anchored in and reinforcing the sanctification that photography bestows on the referent’s existential uniqueness. Brink (2000), in fact, identifies three analogies between religious icons and historic photographs: their ‘intense symbolic impact’, their authenticity or ‘special affinity to reality’, and their canonization, expressed through extensive reproduction and distribution in different media. Yet, while iconic photographs are canonized through repeated circulation , this may also corrode their intensity and uniqueness . Certain kinds of appropriation might lead not to canonization but to desacralization , until the images are devoid of the significance that made them iconic in the first place . The possibilities for such desacralization have been greatly magnified in the new media environment. Iconic photographs in the new media environment The sanctified historic and symbolic power of iconic photographs depended on distinctive practices of image production, dissemination, and alteration that characterized the mass ‘media regime’. These practices have been increasingly destabilized in the contemporary media environment, principally in two overlapping domains: institutions and technology. The key relevant institutional characteristic of the previous regime was the centrality of professional journalism. Key factors for iconic photographs include the role of the professional photojournalist as their primary source – informed by an occupational habitus based on norms of factual and moral ‘witnessing’ (Zelizer, 2007), the importance of editorial and publishing personnel as gatekeepers controlling publication and distribution, and the role of legal and contractual frameworks (e.g. copyright, commercial licensing) in governing, and limiting, processes of replication and alteration. As a consequence, possibilities for republication were mostly made available within journalism, but also within similarly centralized and demarcated institutions, such as book and magazine publishing, advertising and marketing, and the established art world. In most cases, the professional, contractual, and hierarchical structures in play contributed to the sanctification of iconic photographs since their use was sanctioned by legitimate institutions enjoying extensive cultural authority. While aspects of this regime have remained in force, certain important shifts have weakened it. These include the increasing dependence on non-professional user-generated images in the form of citizen journalism (Andén-Papadopoulos and Pantti, 2011), the blurring boundaries and struggles for cultural authority between professional and nonprofessional practitioners and genres (Sjøvaag, 2011), and the spread of user- monitored and participatory editorial models (Deuze, 2003). All these reconfigure the institutional framework for the circulation of iconic photographs in favor of more decentralized, less authoritative, and potentially more democratic uses and appropriations. Technological changes are crucial to these institutional developments. Already existing iconic photographs – the focus of this article – become ‘ networked images’ (Rubinstein and Sluis, 2008) available for instant replication and mass distribution using social network services that bypass traditional gatekeepers , while ubiquitous image manipulation software enables ordinary individuals to disseminate radically altered versions to large audiences. Dependence on software processes for storage, replication, distribution, and display means that iconic photographs – like other fixed media ‘documents’ – have now become impermanent , real-time , dynamic ‘performances’ (Manovich, 2013: 33–34). Such ‘performances’ can raise issues beyond their original audiences and targets , allowing diverse publics to appropriate the iconic photo for new purposes . At the same time, however, these appropriations reveal a fundamental paradox: the more a photograph is recycled, the more it may influence the public – yet the more the original referential context may be lost in the process . For instance, Ibrahim (2016) argues that parodic versions of
the Tiananmen ‘Tank Man’ image express resistance to Chinese state censorship while also being ‘stripped from context, re-hashed and endlessly circulated as cultural artefacts bearing the burden of history yet being disenfranchised from it’ (p. 593). For iconic photographs, recycling is thus a definitional condition and a potential death threat . In a way, iconic photos are victims of their own success , as the diminution of their original reference is a condition for reaching iconic status: when a photograph becomes iconic, it is ‘ revised , circulated , and reissued in various venues until whatever reality its subject first possessed has been drained away’ (Rabinowitz, 1994: 87). The emblematic indexicality of iconic photographs The fit of iconic photographs for public salience and extensive replication hinges on a crucial semiotic duality: they are at once particular and universal, concrete and abstract. Frosh (2012) calls this duality ‘emblematic indexicality’. Peirce’s (1958) concept of indexicality designates signs that ‘point to’ their objects through a causal or physical connection. Photography is usually treated as indexical because the light reflected from the objects and scenes before the camera makes contact with the light-sensitive emulsion (or photoelectric sensors in digital cameras), thereby ‘producing’ the image (Barthes, 1981; Doane, 2007). Anchored spatially and temporally, this indexical character nevertheless runs parallel to ‘emblematic’ or symbolic processes, for two reasons: because the image is also interpreted according to contextual cultural knowledge and conventions of representation and because interpretive procedures generalize the meaning of the objects depicted beyond their specificity; they may ‘stand for’ (a classic definition of representation) absent others, including larger populations, broad historical periods, and abstract concepts. In the case of ‘Accidental Napalm’, the spatial indexical anchors are the human figures and the particular place in which they appear: these figures are identifiable as actual, nameable individuals who were before the camera at the time, including Kim Phuc, the naked girl. The temporal anchor is a precise moment, which can be specified through mechanical measures (date, time). However, these indexical anchors immediately lend themselves to extension and expansion: the spatial anchor is extended to ‘Vietnam’, ‘Vietnamese civilians’, and ‘soldiers’; the temporal anchor to the early 1970s; while contextual cultural knowledge at the moment of its first circulation connects it to the political and moral controversies and disintegrating consensus about the war among the American public. However, with iconic photos the process of symbolic generalization is exceptionally extensive: they connote death, injustice, courage, patriotism, and hope in ways that move beyond the particular political and cultural climates of their first appearance. This universal dimension is afforded by the photo’s particular signifiers, although it frequently also taps into pre-existing symbolic frameworks. For instance, the connection between the suffering of Kim Phuc and the suffering of innocents in general is not simply due to her status as a child (or her nudity, to be discussed below), but to her Christ-like pose. The recycling of iconic photos in different contexts , including with physical modifications, may facilitate and enhance the passage to a universal meaning , by detaching their primary signifiers from their indexical anchors or original contexts. Erasing pictorial elements that point to the Vietnam War, the United States or the 1970s would clarify and ‘unclutter’ the universal meaning of injustice. Yet , our study of the increasing range of appropriations of this photo suggests that the opposite trend may also be at work: not the universalization of the image’s meaning but its narrowing ; not the sacralization of the picture but its trivialization . Benjamin argued that ‘every image of the past that is not recognized by the present as one of its own concerns threatens to disappear irretrievably’ (quoted in Zelizer, 2000: 1). Today, however, the opposite may be true: an image of the past that is recognized by the present as one of its own concerns may be ‘ performed’ and manipulated so often and drastically that it merely becomes one of many existing templates for digital memes .
Deterrence---1NC---OFF Offord says inner disarm causes external disarm. They highlighted a causal line, no take backs Ensures nuclear conflict with China, Russia, North Korea, and Iran. Matthew Kroenig 23 —Professor in the Department of Government and the Edmund A. Walsh School of Foreign Service at Georgetown University. A 2019 study in Perspectives on Politics ranked him as one of the top 25 most-cited political scientists of his generation, 1/12/2023, The Sheathed Sword From Nuclear Brink to No First Use , Prakash Menon (Volume Editor), Aditya Ramanathan (Volume Editor), Chapter 11: US Nuclear Strategy, No First Use, and the Return of Great Power Competition, Bloomsbury Publishing The 2017 National Security Strategy of the USA declares the return of great power competition with Russia and China to be the foremost threat facing the US A and its allies.1 As competition with nuc lear-armed powers has become the foremost priority of US foreign and defence policy, nuc lear weapon s , the ultimate instrument of military force , has once again become a high-priority issue. This chapter will explain US nuclear strategy in an era of great power competition.2 It will argue that the country facing multiple great power adversaries , cannot have a single nuclear strategy but rather need s a tailored and flexible strategy , able to simultaneously deter multiple rivals presenting diverse threats . The chapter will also argue that the USA has never possessed an NFU policy and has always retained the option of using nuclear weapons first in order to deter substantial non-nuclear attacks on itself and its allies. The USA’s reliance on nuclear deterrence is in part a result of its global defence commitments. Despite some support for a US NFU in the far left wing of the US political spectrum, it is unlikely the country will adopt NFU or support a GNFU treaty absent a fundamental reorientation of its grand strategy and foreign and defence policy objectives. The rest of the chapter will continue in five parts. First, it will describe the changed strategic context facing the USA and its allies and partners. Second, it will define the goals for US nuclear strategy. Third, it will articulate the central tenets of a tailored and flexible US nuclear strategy. Fourth, it will discuss the capability requirements for such a strategy. Next, it will explain why NFU would be contrary to core tenets of American nuclear strategy . Finally, it will conclude with some reflections on the future of US nuclear strategy STRATEGIC CONTEXT Nuclear weapons were central to the bipolar, strategic competition between the USA and the Soviet Union during the Cold War. Following the collapse of Communism, however, nuclear weapons receded to the background. Both nuclear superpowers drastically reduced the size of their arsenals in a series of arms-control agreements and by 2010, serious people even discussed the possibility of the global abolition of nuclear weapons.3 These deliberations made sense given the strategic context of the time. The greatest threat to US national security was thought to come from nuclear terrorism and the possibility of conflicts with nuclear powers, such as Russia and China, was described accurately as ‘remote’.4 This reality changed in the mid-2010s. In 2014, Russia invaded Ukraine and made threats against the rest of Europe. In addition, Russia moved nuclear weapons more to the centre of its defence and military strategy. Most concerning is its nuclear ‘escalate-to-de-escalate’ strategy, which calls for the early use of nuc lear weapon s in the event of a conflict with the USA or NATO. 5 In addition, Russia is building the capabilities to support this strategy, including modernising its strategic forces and its large stockpile of non-strategic nuclear weapons . These include shortand intermediate-range nuclear-armed ground-launched missiles, nuclear torpedoes, nuclear depth charges, nuclear sea-launched cruise missiles, nuclear air-launched cruise and ballistic missiles, nuclear surface-to-air missiles for use in
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
air defence and nuclear-tipped missile defence interceptors.6 Furthermore, Russia is building a new generation of nuclear weapons of terror never dreamed of during the Cold War, including a nuclear-armed drone sub marine, a nuclear- powered and nuclear- armed cruise missile and a nuclear-armed hypersonic missile. In short, Russia puts a nuke on almost any imaginable weapons system. Perhaps, the greatest challenge facing the USA is the rise of China. China has also become more aggressive in recent years. Under President Xi, China has thrown away the ‘hide-and-bide’ strategy of Deng Xiaoping and charted a more expansionist course . 7 It is taking contested territory through brute force in the S outh C hina S ea. It is building up its military power with the goal of weakening US alliances and pushing American military power out of Asia. It is also engaging in an ambitious global strategy, including its Belt and Road Initiative (BRI) to use infrastructure investment to increase its geopolitical influence in every major world region. Fortunately, China’s nuclear strategy and posture is more relaxed than Russia’s, but this might be changing. The 2018 US Nuclear Posture Review (NPR) states that, despite its formal NFU pledge, China might use nuclear weapons first in a conflict in Asia. 8 And the US government projects that China will greatly increase the size of its nuclear arsenal in the coming years. 9 No rth Ko rea is on the verge of becoming only the third potential US adversary to possess the ability to deliver nuclear weapons to the US homeland. It is estimated to have dozens of warheads . 10 It has the ability to deliver nuc lear weapon s in its region and could soon have a functioning intercontinental ballistic missile ( ICBM ) capability. Despite years of negotiations, there are few signs that North Korea will denuclearise anytime soon and the US A and its allies must strengthen deterrence now , even as it works towards its stated goal of disarmament. Iran currently poses a non-nuclear strategic threat to the USA and its regional security partners. Iran’s foreign policy and domestic political legitimacy are predicated on resistance to the US A and resistance to the West. It is operating proxy forces in Iraq , Syria , Lebanon and Yemen . Tehran is the world’s largest state sponsor of terror and has backed terror and proxy attacks against the US A and its allies for decades . It has the largest missile programme in the Middle East and is working on longer-range and intercontinental ballistic missiles. Tehran has a sophisticated, offensive cyber programme. It may also possess c hemical and b iological w eapon s . 11 Iran , therefore, has the ability to conduct a non-nuclear attack that could be nuclear-like in its strategic effects. Moreover, it has ceased compliance with the Joint Comprehensive Plan of Action and experts estimate that its dash time to a nuclear weapon might be as little as six to eight months.12 Nuclear terrorism also remains a concern. The threat has dissipated since the immediate post 9/11 era. The operational environment for terrorist groups, such as Al Qaeda and the Islamic State in Iraq and Syria (ISIS), has gotten more difficult. And the USA and its allies have made great strides in securing loose nuclear materials around the world. Still, if a terrorist group acquired nuclear weapons, deterrence would be more challenging (although not impossible).13 In short, the nuclear security environment for the USA and its allies has greatly deteriorated in the past decade. The risk of nuc lear war between the US A and its nuclear-armed rivals may be greater now than at any time since the most dangerous days of the Cold War . This means that the US A must once again prioritise nuclear deterrence in its foreign and defence policy.
Haiku---1NC---OFF king ghidora is an antihero which is worth affirming now Our redaction of their 1AC excludes their performance of the nuclear mundane and reveals the nuclear sublime through haiku and tanka---that’s key to understanding and resisting nuclear violence Miller & Atherton 17 [Alyson Miller and Cassandra Atherton 2017 (“Monster in the sky’: Hibakusha Poetry and the Nuclear Sublime”, Deakin University)] The nuclear sublime is a critical term , first used by Frances Ferguson in 1984. In her article in Diacritics, she begins by identifying a clause in a State Farm insurance policy, which states it will not cover loss ‘involving a nuclear incident’ (1984: 4). Ferguson uses this example to argue that while other disasters can be insured against, ‘nuclear peril’ cannot (4) due to its utter annihilation of the world and all life forms. Drawing on Jonathan Schell’s detailed description of this destruction, she argues that Schell ‘portrays himself as having determined to try and “think the unthinkable ”’ (5), while the insurance policy statement demonstrates the way that State Farm refuses to even attempt to do this. Despite their differing approaches , Ferguson makes the point that both of them are ultimately unsuccessful in discussing nuclear destruction, because of its ultimate sublimity : the nuclear as unthinkable [is] the most recent version of the notion of the sublime, that alternative and counterpoise to the beautiful that was revivified when Longinus’ Peri Hupsous (On Great Writing) was rediscovered in the seventeenth century and became especially influential in the eighteenth (5). This paper examines hibakusha (atomic bomb survivor) poetry as a response to the nuclear sublime. It posits that hibakusha poetry – specifically tanka and haiku – best acknowledge the experience of the atomic bomb as ineffable . This is because of all atomic bomb literature, poetry turns on an economy of expression where fewer words are used to express ideas . In this way, we posit that haiku and tanka, specifically, with their focus on fewer words , lines and syllables than free verse poetry, are the vehicles that most successfully capture atomic experience and its sublimity . That is, we argue that these traditional Japanese poetic forms are uniquely able to express the anguish of the impossibility of describing the trauma of nuclear annihilation, via subtle use of allusion, fragmentation and minimalism . Hibakusha are positioned to be silent , rather than provide political commentary on atomic warfare. This is due to the discrimination they continue to face both at home and abroad , even seventy years after the dropping of the atomic bomb. Robert Jay Lifton has defined their discrimination in terms of the ‘death taint’ (1991: 170), which ‘caus[es] others to turn away and the hibakusha themselves to withdraw’ (170). There is a threefold prejudice: the hibakusha became symbolic of mortality, a reminder of Japan’s loss in war and, to extend these ideas, a symbol of the atomic sublime . The prejudice against hibakusha continues even into the second and third generation because people fear they may have inherited sickness and sterility, and the belief that they may give still give birth to deformed children because of the radiation poisoning. This encourages hibakusha and their progeny to remain silent . Hibakusha poets write into this silence . This is because as survivors they argue they have ‘a sense of duty toward humanity to bear witness in the face of the patent threat to life posed by nuclear weapons’ (Braw 1997: 171)
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
1NC---Case
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
1NC---Case The CORRECT name is King Ghidora. THEIRS is part of a racist whitewash of the film done. It doesn’t solve Ryfle ‘98 (Steve Ryfle, Film reporter and journalist with a specialization in Japanese Cinema and its adaptation to American Audiences. “Japan’s Favorite Mon-Star: The Unauthorized Biography of the Big- G” ISBN: 1-55022-348-8 Pages 116 – 117)//RJG DO THE CONTINENTAL: Within a few months of its release in Japan, the U.S. distribution rights to The Greatest Battle on Earth were acquired by Walter Reade-Sterling inc., a New York company that operated a chain of movie theaters and distributed art house and low-budget films through its subsidiary, Continental. Continental inexplicably shortened the spelling of King Ghidorah's name to "Ghidrah" [sic], retitled the picture Ghidrah : The Three-Headed Monster, and opened it in 83 theaters in Boston on a double bill with a James Bond spoof called Agent 8 3/4 , and later in other areas with the Elvis Presley vehicle Harum Scarum. Continental officials proudly boasted in Variety at the time that Ghidrah earned more than $200,000 in film rentals in its first five days of release and more than $1.3 million overall. But it was blood money ! Unlike the mostly handsoff approach that American International Pictures took with Godzilla vs. The Thing, Continental subjected Ghidrah to an array of unnecessary, annoying, and sometimes incompetent editorial changes , including the removal of scenes, the shifting around of scenes, the replacement of some of Akira Ifukube's marvelous score (including a great theme for the Godzilla-vs.-Rodan sequence, with unique motifs for each monster) with nondescript film library music, and the truncation of the twin fairies' second rendition of the lovely "Cry For Happiness," sung just prior to Mothra's departure from Infant Island. The English dubbing by Joseph Belucci (a former voice actor and director at Titra Sound in New York, who had formed his own dubbing studio) is adequately scripted but dully acted, the lowlight being an off-camera starlet named "Annie Sukiyaki" reading a rough translation of the fairies' song . Their fixation on Japan as victim of Hiroshima and Nagasaki is a tool of colonial empire to nationalize bombings as uniquely Japanese---that actively omits Korean victims of the bombings that relegates colonial anxieties to the past and avoid the history of empire which TURNS case Kramer 23 [DEREK J. KRAMER is a Li Foundation Research Fellow at the University of Cambridge’s Needham Institute. He received his degree in East Asian studies from the University of Toronto. Derek’s work focuses on Cold War technoscientific culture in postcolonial settings.. "An Atomic Age Unleashed: Emancipation and Erasure in Early Korean Accounts of the Hiroshima and Nagasaki Bombings ” MAY 01 2023. https://read-dukeupress-edu.ezproxy.lib.uh.edu/journal-of-asian-studies/article/82/2/144/351270/An-Atomic-Age-UnleashedEmancipation- and-Erasure-in] //ix In early October 1945, three researchers from Kyoto University took the train to Hiroshima . Pak Ch’ŏlchae , Ree T'aegyu , and Ri Sŭnggi were three of the most distinguished Korean scientists of their day . Each held doctorates in the discipline, occupied prestigious laboratory posts in the Japanese metropole, and would go on to have prolific careers in the postcolonial academies of North and South Korea. Their trip was part of a larger pilgrimage by scientists in Japan to the recently devastated city that, along with Nagasaki, had become stark curiosities of an impending atomic age (Kim D. 2005). Months later, following their repatriation to the Korean peninsula, an account of the trip by Pak Ch’ŏlchae appeared in one of Seoul's recently established popular science magazines . The article opened with a description of the devastated city, but this was only a brief prologue. Pak was clearly fixed on the future and, in particular, the possibilities
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
portended by an atomic tomorrow. “The unleashing of the atom is revolutionary,” he explained, “not simply because the particle is cut in two, but because of the enormous energy that is released by doing so” (Pak C. 1946: 21). Excitement over the transformative potential of the atomic attacks fit well with the forward-looking character of the day. After decades of Japanese rule, the Korean peninsula unexpectedly encountered the promises and perils of Cold War decolonization and division. For the writers and translators who took up the subject of the bombings at this time, the atomic age and the postcolonial era were more than just synchronic chapters of history; the two fused into a common mode of articulating political and historical advancement. Amalgamated in this way, early Korean accounts of the Asia-Pacific War emphasized the liberatory utility of atomic weapons, with intellectuals suggesting causal linkages between science, conflict, and progress. These could be powerful sequences of emancipation that brought together stories of national and global advancement. However, by staging the bombings as a preface to a new era of history , intellectuals helped conceal the critical narratives and temporalities repatriated to the peninsula by the Korean survivors of the Hiroshima and Nagasaki attacks. This was a significant act of erasure . The experiences of colonial atomic bomb victims often undermined the political lines ascribed to the end of empire and resisted the sense of rupture assigned to the post-liberation period. However, rather than take up the challenge to the future posed by Korean bomb survivors , writers and translators from across the peninsula tended to sidestep the violence of the attacks and their aftermath. In doing so, Korean intellectuals participated in the omission of colonial subjects from their stories of the bombings, relegating the active and critical anxieties of this group to the past . Themes of exclusion and erasure have long framed scholarship on Korean atomic bomb survivors . Largely focused on struggles with the Japanese state, research on this group has effectively demonstrated the multivalent forms of discrimination that first brought Koreans , often as forced laborers and draftees, to the metropole and then, following the bombings, forced them to leave (Tong 1991; Toyonaga 2001; Palmer 2006; Takahashi 2018; Wake 2021). A manifestation of what has been termed an “ ethnic-epistemological trap ,” the Japanese state structurally marginalized colonial populations in official documentation , which in turn facilitated their disappearance in later historical accounts (Kawashima 2009). This absence effectively buttressed a political approach to the commemoration of the atomic attacks that nationalized the bombings as a specifically Japanese experience (Saito 2006; Orr 2001). During the 1960s and 1970s, minority histories, restorative activism, and commemorative events developed by and around the Korean community of Japan agitated against this erasure. Such interventions often employed biographical narratives that connected the experience of the bombings and their aftermaths to persistent structures of colonial relations (Yoneyama 1999; Ropers 2015; Saito 2017; Takahashi 2018; Duró 2018). By the 1990s and early 2000s, an increased number of South Korean works on and by peninsular bomb victims further underlined the links between the experience of the atomic attacks and imperial legacies (Oh 2018; Yang 2019). By way of this enriched scope, the story of Korean atomic bomb survivors has contributed to the broader reckoning with the politics of narration, memory, and empire that has defined the past generation of research on twentieth-century East Asia. It is in this broader context that the removal of colonial populations from accounts of the bombings can be convincingly taken as emblematic for the broader avoidance of empire in histories of modern Japan itself (Schmid 2000; Choi 2021). S uch instances of erasure illustrate the ways that nationalism persists as an organizing mechanism in the histories of former empires . Here the exclusive scope of the nation fits squarely with the political conventions of a polity eager to leave the story of empire behind. Their framing of godzillla recreates the techno-orientalism they critique Lu 21 [Melanie Lu, Asian Studies, 4-2021-21, "Gendering the Techno-Orient: The Asian Woman in Speculative Fiction," Vanderbilt,
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
https://ir.vanderbilt.edu/bitstream/handle/1803/16493/LuMelanie_VUIRSubmission.pdf? sequence=1&isAllowed=y] [accessed 10-14-2023] lydia Specifically, we need to first consider the ways in which Japan’s interactions with the west throughout modern history inform the technological ideologies manifest in Japanese animation and even popular culture in general. Scholars have long noted that Japan’s complicated wartime history as both aggressor and victim has led to reinterpretations and allegorizations of the atomic bombings and postwar U.S occupation in popular media , inspiring many narratives of monstrous catastrophe, apocalypse, and invasion, along with representations of international (especially U.S-Japan) relations fraught with economic and technological tension (Bolton 32). Perhaps the long-running Godzilla franchise comes to mind, now with 36 total iterations that inherit the original 1954 film’s allegorization of nuclear disaster to various degrees. In the context of this fixation with the monstrous and hyper-technological , Sharalyn Orbaugh has further suggested that not only are Japanese viewers consistently engaged with portrayals of robots, cyborgs, and the “mecha ” genre (giant mechanical fighting suits), but they also share an affinity for the technological paradigm because of what she calls the “Frankenstein syndrome .” This is an inflection of Rey Chow’s coinage of “King Kong syndrome,” which originally delineates the west’s Orientalist framing and spectatorship of Asia as a site of mutation and monstrosity, an unrestrained culture of excess devoured by its own technology (Orbaugh 174). Orbaugh’s term, however, refers to the Orient’s internalization, and even reproduction, of that framing, in which Asians and specifically the Japanese see themselves through the very lens that have constructed them as technological Other. In a similar vein, Toshiya Ueno proposes that Japanese animation not only acts as a distorting mirror through which the west misconstrues the Japanese as automata-like “Japanoids,” but that it also serves as “the mechanism through which Japanese [people] misunderstand themselves ” a s they internalize techno- Orientalism (Ueno 95). These techno-political anxieties pervade Ghost in the Shell as well. They’re responsible for matching up the scope of solvency with the scope of their impacts. Presenting concrete, legal solutions improves critical purchase and avoids cooption. Visoka, 19 —Associate Professor of Peace and Conflict Studies at Dublin City University (Gëzim, “Critique and Alternativity in International Relations,” International Studies Review, Volume 21, Issue 4, December 2019, 678-704, dml) Critical IR theory needs to make more space for self-reflexivity and to open up to an epistemic transformation. The preceding discussion demonstrated that although peace and conflict studies are more pluralist than other critical IR branches , they are still affected by paradigmatic and disciplinary divides within IR. They operate in a conflictual theorizing logic that disregards certain ontological, methodological, and epistemological alternatives in order to remain loyal to one particular disciplinarity . For Laura Sjoberg (2017, 163–67), “disciplinarity has a narrowing effect,” suggesting that “an undisciplined IR would free space for more radical critique and more radical experimentation.” Disciplinary encampment among different branches of critical IR has suffocated the search for achievable emancipatory possibilities across a different range of cases. Endorsing alternativity requires a fluid onto-epistemology that would make it possible to bypass the epistemological entrapments caused by rigid academic rules of thought and of knowledge production and by the academic research process. Nonconflictual pathways of research would be beneficial for overcoming paradigmatic contempt, bypassing methodological holism and individualism, and making space for conciliatory heuristics and reality- congruent inquires (see Archer 1995; Hamati-Ataya 2018). Searching for nonconflictual critiques that are embedded in postparadigmatic logic means generating conceptually novel and reality-congruent knowledge about conflict-affected societies and the broader politics of
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
international interventions. This should not be seen as an attempt to discipline the discipline of peacebuilding studies. On the contrary, it would be an attempt to break away from disciplinary entrenchments that have impeded a better understanding of complexity in postconflict societies. It would also be an attempt to avoid the normalization of entrenched research programs and open up the politics of knowledge production on peace, conflict, security, justice, and development. More broadly, alternativity in critical IR theory needs to be rescued from never-ending conceptual reifications , which have ended up making ontological assentation about the world become completely detached from the world . In this regard, there is a growing realization in IR that critique is a necessary but secondary task; the priority is to return to practical theory as quickly as possible (Levine 2012, 69). Recalibrating the purpose of alternativity in critical theory requires recalibrating knowledge production, not only to unmask power relations and the dynamics of dominance and to create space for a politics of resistance but also to generate practical knowledge for political action that challenges, confronts, and disrupts existing power relations and offers alternative solutions for reshuffling social relations on more emancipatory and inclusive terms (see Duvall and Varadarajan 2003, 85; Murdie 2017; Deiana and McDonagh 2018). A feature of critical peace and conflict studies is a congruence between the emancipatory and problem- solving perspectives, which should be predicated on the conciliation of knowledge, the expansion of onto-politics of peace, and the pluralization of epistemological and methodological approaches. The recent methodological work by J. Samuel Barkin and Laura Sjoberg (2017) on interpretive quantification is a promising move toward this much-needed pluralist fertilization within critical theory. In particular, a stronger linkage between criticality, alternativity, and practicality could help critical security, peace, and conflict theories to offer alternatives that would maintain critical impetus while simultaneously strengthening ties to practical and societal problem-addressing solutions . Genealogical studies would blend well with a critical analysis of conceptual and policy alternatives (see Milliken 1999). Statistical analysis with an emancipatory hypothesis coupled with critical analysis would contribute to subverting policy practices and would normalize alternative knowledge about peace, justice, and emancipation. The recent practice-turn in IR offers new bridges between scholars and practitioners, making it possible to translate critical knowledge into practice without compromising the normativity and criticality of scholarly works (see Bigo 2011). A forum on pragmatism published in this journal has implicitly highlighted the importance of alternativity in understanding global politics and generating impactful knowledge beyond the existing epistemological and methodological divides (see Hellmann 2009). Friedrichs and Kratochwil (2009, 701) have argued for “the orientation of research toward the generation of useful knowledge .” Practicality is essential for generating alternatives . For instance, Jonna Nyman (2016, 142) argues that “ a pragmatic , practice-centred approach . . . can help us gain practical knowledge of how security works and understand the value of security better, as well as help us to suggest alternative possibilities .” Similarly, Navnita Chadha Behera (2016, 154) argues: “ theorizing in IR needs to step out of the rarefied atmosphere of its academe, develop a healthy scepticism toward its canonical frames, and open up to the possibilities of learning from everyday life and experiences of people and their living traditions and practices.” Practicality shifts the focus from abstract criticality and normativity to contextual critiques that account for everyday practices and interactions. This would be essential for rescuing critique from becoming a postempirical endeavor. Critical knowledge that engages with policy alternatives “is not only pragmatic , it is also politically enabling : it forces us away from instrumental problem-solving perspectives towards a wider framework of pragmatic thought where narrow instrumental goals are overridden by wider normative and political concerns” (Kurki 2013, 260). Such grounded critiques are crucial in order to expand non-prescriptive alternativity and exploring practical possibilities for social emancipation and change . For Steve Smith (2002: 202), “ the acid test for the success of alternative and critical approaches is the extent to which they have led to empirically grounded work that explores the range and variety of world politics .” This would also be congruent with Daniel Levine's (2012, 30) concept of sustainable critique , which entails thinking in both practical and critical terms at once so that “IR could create a sustainably critical perspective on global politics that might then be turned back onto , and
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
made to inform , ongoing policy debates and discourses.” Behera (2016, 154) further maintains that the “state-centric ontology of IR has effectively ended up dehumanizing the discipline in a way so that normally it has little to do with human relations, human needs, and the larger imperatives of humanity.” Generating practical alternatives would therefore require endorsing situated knowledge as an epistemological and methodological basis for any engagement with the real world. The work of feminists such as Donna Haraway (1988, 584) on situated standpoints is also relevant here because they offer “more adequate, sustained, objective, transforming accounts of the world.” Situated knowledge is, mostly, nonrepresentational knowledge, in that it is not firmly mediated through preexisting discourses. In this regard, promoting subjugated knowledge discourses and practices could be central to rejuvenating the emancipatory commitment of critical theory (see Doty 1996). Situated alternatives could derive from emplaced and embodied knowledge and could have a more emancipatory character as they “bring forth the importance of recognizing, valuing, and employing marginalized voices by working from this perspective, as well as by reshaping research to include marginalized communities as part of knowledge production” (McHugh 2015, 62). For Robson and McCartan (2016, 3), “ real world research looks to examine personal experience, social life and social systems, as well as related policies and initiatives . It endeavours to understand the lived in reality of people in society and its consequences .” Milja Kurki's (2013, 245) recent study of democracy promotion has approached alternativity from the perspective of policy provocations , which focus “on not prioritising one or another perspective, but rather on encouraging self-reflection by all practitioners, which in turn is considered as a key condition of seeking adequately pluralism-fostering reforms in concrete policy frameworks .” Kurki (2013, 248–51) further maintains that “instead of relying on objective knowledge and criteria, policy process can and should be attuned to the logic of interpretive, politicised and participatory judgements.” Her study is an excellent example of pragmatic congruence between criticality and alternativity, whereby policy alternatives are not geared toward totally improving or enhancing the current system but openly promote more pluralistic, reflexive, and emancipatory policies for democratization and peacebuilding. Moreover, for these new grounds of critical alternativity to be introduced in practice, knowledge production should be decentered, decolonized, and “de-methodolised” (see Lisle 2014). R. B. J. Walker (2002, 265) has argued that “the key achievement of supposedly alternative and critical literatures over the past two decades has been to open up at least some possibility of asking questions about the location and character of the political.” As elaborated in this study, knowledge production in peace and conflict studies is predominantly based on Western epistemologies, which are shaped by specific cultures of thought, self-perpetuated epistemological superiority, and codified academic practices. Most of the international scholarship on postconflict societies derives from an unrepresentative body of knowledge, which tries to mediate, deviate, reinterpret, and, consequently, construct a different social reality that is interpreted through different measurements, reference points, and analytical concepts (see Latour 2005). This has greatly limited the possibility for proposing realizable alternatives. Due to these epistemological anomalies, there are growing calls in scholarship to decolonize knowledge from Eurocentric and Western dominance and instead to pursue more pluralist and particularist modes of knowledge (Smith 2012). For instance, Acharya and Buzan (2010, 2) have argued that IR theory should be “an open domain into which it is not unreasonable to expect non- Westerners to make a contribution at least proportional to the degree that they are involved in its practice.” Similarly, Andrew Hurrell (2016, 151) has proposed that “the pathway to a global IR will need to look beyond ‘IR’ and is likely to require new models for organizing social science research and knowledge production.” Decolonized epistemologies of peace would reverse the order of knowledge, placing the local first and then the regional and international as spatial and ontological scales for understanding peace processes (Visoka 2017). They would not operate in isolation but would engage in shaping global IR knowledge. Therefore, a genuine search for achievable alternatives should try to decolonize peace knowledge from Western and Eurocentric frameworks, interrogate decolonized knowledge and agencies, and explore the joint constitution of international intervention and local resistance (see Smith 2012; Memmi 2006). Local scholars often have rich knowledge, but the primary usage of it is not for instrumental purposes or for transferring and sharing with audiences of outsiders. Local knowledge is very much used to respond to narrow practical and everyday interests and needs and, as such, is embedded in the logic of generating sufficient knowledge to respond to specific circumstances. In the context of peacebuilding, as examined in this article, generating alternatives from the ground up has the potential to bring about more sustainable forms of peace and reconciliation for groups and societies affected by violent conflict. Situated alternatives for emancipatory peace are more prone to avoiding co-optation by positivist and problem-solving epistemic predators, resulting thus in developing pluriversal political and peace orders beyond liberal peacebuilding and other Eurocentric impositions. From this situated perspective, emancipation could take the shape of “the transformation of structures and relationships of vulnerability through localized political action, aimed at the creation of spaces in people's lives so that they are enabled to make decisions and act beyond mere survival” (Basu and Nunes 2013, 69). Emancipatory alternatives would not be universal in their applications because such an attempt is not viable . Rather the focus should be on searching for practical emancipatory possibilities within a given context , time, space, and place (see Fierke 2007, 24). In other words, critiques with an adequate dose of alternativity are more likely to generate globally understandable and locally impactful knowledge . Nevertheless, alternativity does not necessarily have to be predicated on representative views of the world—it can also be a by-product of performing hope and imagined possibilities in global politics . Shapiro (2013, xiv) argues that critical thinking helps to “create the conditions of possibility for imaging alternative worlds.” That said, as the purpose of critical
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
theory is emancipatory change, any alternative theoretical and empirical observation in service of improving the human conditions should generate a morally and practically acceptable standpoint. Because any attempt to establish an alternative interpretation inevitably “empowers a particular social and political standpoint” (Price and Reus-Smit 1998, 261). According to Ní Mhurchú and Shindo (2016, 5), “critique can help us to develop different ways of talking about, evaluating, doing and interrogating the changing nature of politics, relations and experiences of the international in a globalising world.” Hence, critique is inevitably implicated in world-making and, with a much clearer understanding of alternativity, can steer the thrust for world-changing in a more emancipatory, just, and inclusive direction. Conclusion Emancipation is a central feature of critical IR debates, but scholars often fail to develop alternatives or solutions achieving emancipation in practice . This article has examined the relationship between criticality and alternativity in IR in order to shed light on some of the most contested issues of critical theory, namely, the epistemological pathways for identifying the inconsistencies and flaws in existing knowledge and practices and the extent to which critical knowledge should generate alternative emancipatory possibilities. The article has argued that alternativity provides an opportunity for critical scholars to remain relevant without being affiliated with positivist logics of inquiry. In unpacking the conceptual contours, the article first explored how different branches of critical IR engage with the episteme of alternativity. The analysis found that although alternativity is often affiliated with problem-solving epistemologies, it has played a major role in shaping critical knowledge in IR. While this is acknowledged and endorsed at the epistemological level by a branch of critical scholars who engage in normative and reconstructive modes of critique, other scholars embedded in deconstructive modes of critique have disregarded the merits of alternativity in IR. The article has argued that, contrary to what is often assumed, alternativity is not incompatible with deconstructive or reconstructive critiques across different subdisciplines of IR. Yet critical IR debates , which have now become the new mainstream in IR, have failed to engage with the episteme of alternativity in a more empirical and practical sense. They preach emancipation but fail to develop tangible emancipatory alternatives . As a result, there is a growing realization that, without tangible alternativity , critical theory risks losing its normative impetus and its ethical and emancipatory commitment , potentially becoming a post-epistemological vocation without politics . Critical knowledge without a dose of alternativity may examine the causes and consequences of subject matters but could fall short of reaching out to the wider policy community and the affected subjects where power relations reside , thus missing the opportunity to transform the structural, discursive, and performative practices that reproduce violence , inequality, and injustice on human and nonhuman ecology. To bridge this epistemological gap, the analysis in the second part of this article examined how alternativity features in peace and conflict studies, a disciplinary field known for adding normative, empirical, and practical substance to critical IR debates. The analysis offered a conceptual scoping of three modes of critique and alternativity in peace and conflict studies. The three modes of critique showed that a conjunction between criticality and alternativity is possible and that it is necessary to renew the practical and emancipatory potential of critical theory in IR. The three modes of alternativity in peace and conflict studies expose a spectrum of different critiques, ranging from those perspectives that disengage completely from conceptual and empirical alternatives, to more pragmatic and prescriptive approaches. Critique-without-alternative represents one strand, which tends to avoid offering normative and practical alternatives to their critical reflections aimed at maintaining the conservative and radical impetus of critical theory and dissociating from problem- solving and policy-relevant methods of inquiry. This mode of critique is committed to revealing the weaknesses of peacebuilding interventions but refuses to offer any emancipatory and practical alternative on how to build sustainable peace after violent conflict. If the end goal of critical perspectives is achieving emancipation, then critique should not only be directed toward problematizing dominant discourses, practices, and policies but also needs to envisage political and practical alternatives rooted in ideational and material elements . In turn, the lack of an explicit emancipatory agenda limits their social and political impact and unintentionally validates the existing order . In response to this challenge, a new mode of critique has emerged, namely, critique-as-alternative , which exemplifies the optimal approach. Proponents of critique-as-alternative have remained committee to critical analysis, but most importantly, they have taken up the challenge of offering emancipatory knowledge that has practical relevance for vulnerable societies in global politics. Their main flaw , however, has been their inability to elaborate sufficiently their practical and emancipatory alternatives —a flaw that has opened up space for epistemic contestation and policy co-optation. Finally, the third mode of critique—critique-with-alternative—which is embedded in a positivist, problem-solving, and policy-driven logic of inquiry, offers alternatives that seek either to verify existing knowledge and the existing interventionary order or to reject other critical alternatives. Looking at different
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
modes of critique through the lens of alternativity in IR's subdiscipline of peace and conflict studies has provided interesting insights on the promise and limits of critical IR in shaping global politics. The analysis found that existing modes of critique have failed to develop elaborative emancipatory alternatives at both the conceptual and the practical levels. To infuse critique-with-alternative with emancipatory elements, expand the epistemological scope of critique-without-alternative, and operationalize further the practical solutions offered by this mode of critique, substantial changes are needed. This article has suggested exploring postparadigmatic approaches of inquiry in order to avoid existing epistemological entrapments and limitations, reclaiming the practical relevance of critical theory through pragmatic, reflexive, and situated alternatives—across the conceptual, normative, and empirical spectrums—and promoting decolonized, bottom-up methods of knowledge production. The existing modes of critique require pursuing more nonconflictual and postparadigmatic epistemologies, embracing situated knowledge and reclaiming and expanding its practical relevance, breaking away from geo-epistemological hierarchies, and opening up to post- Western IR. To conclude, promoting alternativity has the potential to rejuvenate critical scholarship embedded in the ethos of impactful engagement with the world without being co-opted by the policy world. The next challenge for scholars should not be whether alternativity and criticality are congruent but how emancipatory alternatives can renew the social and political purpose of critical theory and make an impact in the real world . The US isn’t inevitably imperialist. Michael Walzer 14 , a professor emeritus at the Institute for Advanced Study (IAS) in Princeton. Walzer was first employed in 1962 in the politics department at Princeton University. He stayed there until 1966, when he moved to the government department at Harvard. He taught at Harvard until 1980, when he became a permanent faculty member in the School of Social Science at the Institute for Advanced Study. He is co-editor of Dissent and he has written 27 books and published over 300 articles, essays, and book reviews in Dissent, The New Republic, The New York Review of Books, The New Yorker, The New York Times, Harpers, and many philosophical and political science journals. – “A Foreign Policy for the Left” - Dissent – Spring, 2014 – obtained via OmniFile Full Text Select (H.W. Wilson) database The second shortcut, perhaps even more popular than the first, is to stand up always against “imperialism” —or, a shortcut inside the shortcut, always to oppose American policies abroad. Anti-Americanism is a common left politics, which, again, sometimes gets things right, and sometimes doesn’t. I believe that it got things right in Vietnam in 1967; it mostly got things right from the beginning of the twentieth century to the end in Central and South America; it got Iran right in 1953 (when leftists criticized the anti-Mossadegh coup), and Iraq in 2003; it gets NAFTA right, and the IMF, too. But that’s still not enough to make it a reliable shortcut. Remember that the defeat of Nazism and Stalinism, the two most brutal political regimes in world history, was in significant ways American work . This was work that many people on the left supported, as we should have. In 1967 Dwight Macdonald wrote to Mary McCarthy that the American war in Vietnam proved “that despite all the good things about our internal political-social-cultural life, we have become an imperialist power, and one that, partly because of these domestic virtues, is a most inept one.” We have continued to be inept: in December 2005, with 100,000 American soldiers in Iraq, we organized an election— and our man came in third. This is a result, I think, without precedent in imperial history. Macdonald’s understanding of U.S. imperialism reflects a political intelligence and a moral balance that is mostly missing in contemporary anti-American writing. The anti-American shortcut sometimes produces a short-circuited politics as in the Syrian case where left ist writers predicted terrible consequences if the Americans inter - vened on the side of the anti-Assad forces. The predictions have come true even though the U nited S tates didn’t intervene, but once it was clear that the awfulness was not America’s fault, many leftists simply lost interest — except for an ongoing but not very effective engagement on behalf of the war’s victims. Who was responsible for the ongoing war, for the killing , the terror, and the refugee crisis; what social forces were involved; what should we (on the left) make of them and how should we respond to them ? This kind of analysis , standard in left critiques of impe - rialism , has mostly been missing. One reason for its absence is that it offers no opportunity to criticize America; a second reason is that it would require a close reading and sharp critique of Islamist politics. Another much-used shortcut (though it doesn’t work in the Syrian case) is to oppose everything Israel does and to blame it for much that it hasn’t done, since it is the “lackey” of American imperialism or, alternatively, the dominant force in shaping American foreign policy. The policies of the current Israeli government require radical criticism—the occupation, the settlements, the refusal to suppress Jewish hooliganism on the West Bank. Nonetheless, the anti-Israel shortcut is an example, to paraphrase August Bebel, of the leftism of fools. The last shortcut is simply to support every government that calls itself leftist or anti-imperialist and sets itself against American interests. This is different from the old Stalinist shortcut: support the Soviet Union whatever it does because it is the first proletarian dictatorship and the first workers’ paradise. That kind of politics is, I think, definitively finished, though it had a brief afterlife, focused on China and then, with very few believers, on Albania and North Korea. The more recent version celebrates Maximal Leaders like Nasser, Castro, or Hugo Chávez— along with occasional short-lived infatuations, as in the case of Michel Foucault and the future Ayatollah Khomeini. Leftist enthusiasm for populist dictatorships is one of our sad stories, which ends when resources run out, the failure to build the economy is suddenly apparent, and the military takes over. But often the Maximal Leader is a military man himself, and the repressive role of the army simply becomes more obvious over time. In Latin America today, the better left is repre - sented by socialists and social democrats who reject demagogic populism and struggle to produce economic growth, greater equality, and a stronger welfare state—and who attract less enthusiasm from American leftists than they deserve. Most leftists are idealists, and so we tend to idealize other people and to imagine that the world is more hospitable to our ideas than it actually is. At the same time, we know better; so I call this the politics of pretending.
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
Consider the response of many leftists to the al Qaeda attack of 9/11. They argued that the United States should call the attack a crime and look to the UN and the International Criminal Court to deal with the criminals. That was the “Dial 911” response to 9/11 (it has been repeated again and again in response to later terrorist attacks), and it would have made sense if we lived in a world that was actually run by the UN and the ICC. But, as I argued in Dissent at the time, there was no one answering the phone at 911. Self-help isn’t, indeed, the only effective and justified response to criminal attacks; different forms of mutual assistance and collective security are possible, and the left should take a forward position in exploring them. But self-help has to be part of the story, given the world we live in, and it isn’t a good idea to pretend otherwise. Another example: some leftists who opposed the Kosovo intervention argued that it didn’t have what every legal and justified use of force requires: UN authorization. Indeed, it didn’t. The UN Security Council is incapable, almost all the time, of acting in a timely way. Think of the Vietnamese invasion of Cambodia to shut down the killing fields; or the Indian invasion of East Pakistan, now Bangladesh, to end the terror there; or the Tanzanian invasion of Uganda to overthrow the murderous regime of Idi Amin. None of these had or could have gotten UN approval. Many leftists opposed each of these interventions, pretending that the UN was already what leftists want it to be, an effective political agent. It isn’t that, and so the unilateral use of force is often, as Jürgen Habermas said of the Kosovo case, “illegal but morally necessary.” The best and last example of left ist pretending is the insistence on the reason - ableness of people who give no sign of being reasonable. Paul Berman writes of the large numbers of French socialists who supported the Munich Agreement that “they gazed across the Rhine and simply refused to believe that millions of upstanding Germans had enlisted in a political movement whose animating principles were paranoid conspiracy theories [and] blood-curdling hatreds. . . .” In the same spirit, many leftists were eager to describe the Chinese communists as “agrarian reformers.” And many today have been quick to grant the legitimacy of Islamist opposition to American bases in Saudi Arabia, say, or to the exis - tence of Israel—and to ignore the demand for a shari’a state and the radical subordination of women. I am fairly sure that most of the people involved in all these cases knew, deep down, that they were pretending. There is a lot to be said for the default position. We should work in the place we know best to make things better. The improvement of humanity begins at home. This argument has special force for Americans, who live in an increasingly inegalitarian society that is also a near-hegemonic world power: we need to be wary of adventures abroad that make our work at home more difficult. Still, good leftists can’t avoid internationalism. We can’t escape what Václav Havel in 1993 called “the feeling of co- responsibility for the world .” Our deepest commitment is solidarity with people in trouble, and some of the worst troubles —poverty, hunger, tyranny, and mass murder—are being experienced right now in other people’s countries. So we are going to be engaged again and again in arguments about what we can do to help. There is no magic al way of getting these arguments right. But certain ideological positions, rigidly held , are almost certain to get them wrong : that the use of force is never justified ; that “imperial” powers , like the U nited S tates, can never act well in the world; and that revo - lutionaries and fighters for liberation, populist leaders and political vanguards, must never be criticized. In all these cases, ideological commitment means that we will only get things right by accident. Political intelligence and moral sensitivity work much better than ideology, and it is these two that should guide our choice of comrades and our decisions about when and how to act abroad. Dictators and terrorists are never our comrades, but only those men and women who really believe in, and who practice, democracy and equality. We should act abroad only with those who share our commitments, and we should act only in ways consistent with those commitments. Leftists have done that often in the past, but often also, we have not: we have mistaken or betrayed our comrades and acted in ways that did not serve either democracy or equality. We need to learn from our history— and the first lesson is this: no more shortcuts , no more pretending. Discoursive resistance fails Naomi Zack 16 . professor of philosophy at the University of Oregon. She is author and editor of a dozen books, including White Privilege and Black Rights: The Injustice of U.S. Police Racial Profiling and Homicide (2015); The Ethics and Mores of Race: Equality after the History of Philosophy (2011); Ethics for Disaster (2009). Applicative Justice: A Pragmatic Empirical Approach to Racial Injustice. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Incorporated. Pages 125-134. ACADEMIC INJUSTICE DISCOURSE Just law can coexist with unjust practice and both are parts of “ empirical law or what Bendey called “the process of government .” Empirical law is constantly changing and some theorists are optimistic that verbal discourse has the ability to make written law more just, even though the same unjust practices recur or new ones emerge. These theorists , some of whom are or may aspire to become public intellectuals, hope that someday public political discourse on behalf of those who are treated unjustly will have the power to interrupt a cycle of just written law accompanied by continued unjust practice . That is, the “right” discourse perennially holds the promise of changing the beliefs , values, and goals of everyone in the public auditorium , so that the same kind of unjust practices do not perpetually chase the same kinds of just laws .11 This search for magic words is futile for academics who are professionally confined to dry and abstract prose . Our verbiage does not have the power to move the multitudes who do not read or listen to it anyway . But even when multitudes are inspired and emotionally stirred by great orators, action that follows is
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
unlikely to result in lasting change, without the support of powerful interests . After the 1960s, academics began a robust practice of liberatory discourse about injustice that seems to grow more impassioned and intense each year. The quest for demographic diversity among students and faculty in higher education has weathered judicial defeat of explicit affirmative action policies, but only partly for the sake of justice. There are pragmatic prizes if the academy can justify itself by producing a racially integrated leadership and managerial class for business, politics, and the military. Top leaders throughout society realize that they need such racial diversity for broad consumption, voter support, and boots on the ground, and the expression of that need is evident in amicus curiae briefs submitted to the US Supreme Court as it has been torturously dismantling affirmative action, piece by piece, since Bakke in 1978.12 Academic political discourse has been deeper than polemics and debate, exactly because of its disciplined intellectual origins in different fields of study (i.e., discipline imposed by distinct “disciplines”). But it has been swimming upstream against a more rarefied and older academic tradition , particularly among many philosophers and their gate keepers outside of the profession. Even Hannah Arendt (see chapter 2) spoke approvingly of the life of the mind as cut off from real political activity that occurred in the realm of “opinion.” In her 1970 interview with Adelbert Reif, Arendt addressed the phenomenon of college-stu-dent protestors, noting that they had brought social change through optimistic belief in their ability to make a better world, while at the same time discovering joy in civic participation. Arendt credited such protests with the success of the civil rights movement and progress toward ending the Vietnam War.13 As discussed in chapter 4, it is doubtful that Arendt was correct that student protests caused the success of the civil rights movement. A historical analysis of the end to the Vietnam War is beyond the present scope, but what we already know about empirical Bentleyan analyses would warrant skepticism about Arendt’s causal thesis there as well. In the same interview, Arendt warned that demonstrations by student activists could be self-defeating in democratic Euro-American contexts, because in attacking their universities, they were attacking the very entities that made their protests possible, American universities, especially large state schools that were the sites of the protests Arendt had in mind, have perforce developed very different financial structures since 1970. These schools have become increasingly dependent on private corporate and philanthropic funding, with state government funds now a much reduced part of their budget. While this structural change is not generally viewed as an incursion on academic freedom, it has been coincident with a very flat era of student protest and activism. Still, Arendt's notion of the "life of the mind” remains useful if we consider that the progressive/change-seeking output of professional academics since 1970 has been professionally accepted in the institutions that employ its participants. Also, much of today’s liberatory academic discourse can be viewed as the legacy of earlier student protest, furthering a tradition that may have been founded when some of the 1960s student radicals became professors. This indicates that the connection between academic radicals and the hands that feed them is not as simple as Arendt thought. In the United States, everything now points to both the existence of real academic freedom and its real ineffectiveness . Progressive academic writers ply a craft of formal speech that deals with contemporary injustice through complex theoretical frameworks , with requisite scholarly apparatuses and without translation into more simple views of the world ; there is often also a lack of translation from one discipline to another or between subdisciplines in the same field. The audience is other academics and students . Neither specialization nor the limited and partly captive audience should be viewed as problematic because that is the nature of academic work, given broad social divisions of labor. But there is a problem with the delusional nature of so much of this work . The delusion consists of a naive view of the power of academic speech to directly change reality . The rhetorical mode of address used by academics writing cultural criticism , political philosophy, social philosophy, or what is now called social-political philosophy (which combines the other subfield approaches), often proceeds as though its authors are making grand entries in a planetary cabala , where words have the immediate power to become their intended referents . Those who do not write and speak cabalistically may subscribe to the Trickle-Down Good Ideas Theory that can be traced from Plato to John Stuart Mill to John Rawls. Subscription to that theory is immediately self-flattering , but it lacks reliable empirical support .16 Although, after the US civil rights movement, there has been an uncanny coincidence of race-blind formal racial equality with the hegemony in political philosophy of Rawls’s requirement that those who plan fundamental social institutions do so in ignorance of their own societal environments. As we saw in chapter 1, Rawls was quite explicit about this: I assume that the parties do not know the particular circumstances of their own society. That is, they do not know its economic or political situation, or the level of civilization and culture it has been able to achieve. The persons in the original position have no information as to which generation they belong.17 Both race-blind racial equality and Rawlsian ideals are compatible with race-based real inequality. There are, of course, counter-examples, such as Katherine MacKinnon’s work on sexual harassment in the workplace as expressed in current law and institutional policy.18 Nevertheless even very good academic political discourse about justice and injustice cannot be relied up on to attract implementation or application in real life . This may be because there has not been sufficient time for the development of training programs for a new profession of “bridgers,” who could translate good ideas in the academy
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
for those who govern and make policy . An internal problem for such translators would be to decide where to anchor their bridges in fields—every humanistic field—where experts disagree. However, the current tradition of progressive academic writing and speech is less than half a century old and if and when such translators emerge, they will develop their own professional criteria for choosing among contending experts. Public media, as a democratic analogue to disagreement within academic discourse, supports the idea that expressing and airing views in day-to-day practices or special “national conversations” also have immediate practical results . It is not evident how there could be such results , when opposing views and opinions are treated with the same respect and have equal access to the same mass auditorium that lacks rules for evidence or valid argument . As with academic discourse, there is no structured connection to official decision processes. The only reliable result of participation in such unbinding referenda is that those who participate are able to express themselves and get attention that may benefit them in the marketplace of their related endeavors. Public expression also serves to, represent and create collective atmospheres of belief, attitude, and opinion. These atmospheres are implicitly known by a majority of people in the culture, even though such knowledge is difficult to validate. Ambiguities cannot be resolved by recourse to public opinion polls, because understanding the results of those polls requires creative interpretive skills that draw on what is already known about relevant atmospheres. For example, suppose that more blacks than whites believe that white privilege is real and that O.J. Simpson was innocent, or that more whites than blacks believe that white American police officers are not, in general, racially biased. Are the views of whites evidence of racial bias or racial oblivion? Are the views of blacks evidence of racial preference or paranoia? Moreover, such polls almost always have a large racial overlap of opinion: If 29 percent of blacks compared to 71 percent of whites believe X, then 71 percent of blacks and 29 percent of whites do not believe X. Does this mean that the percentages of each group that does not contribute to the discrepancy in belief recorded in the polls are in some degree of agreement? Experiments in social psychology could be designed to answer such questions and others like them, but it is important to decide beforehand why the data is important and what it does and does not indicate. For instance, testing the claim that white privilege is a reality of contemporary life requires some prior definition of what is meant by “white privilege,” which can range from injustice to social courtesies. In a widely discussed 2013 experiment conducted in Queensland, Australia, economists Redzo Mujcic and Paul Frijters found that the majority of free bus rides, based on conductor generosity, were dispensed to whites, with blacks least likely to receive this courtesy, compared to all other racial groups among commuters. Journalist Britni Danielle, writing for a general audience on Yahoo News, touted this study as evidence that “white privilege is real,” without distinguishing between an amenity such as a free bus ride and recognition of one’s rights by not being subject to arbitrary stops and frisks by police officers.19 Conservatives reading Mujcic and Frijter’s study might say that the bus driver may have been acting rationally based on past experience with unruly black passengers. From a progressive perspective, more specifics would need to be introduced to defend the claim that this study revealed white privilege, such as controls for the apparent social class and gender of passengers, as well as the preexisting racial climate among bus commuters in Queensland, as well as the broader racial atmosphere throughout Australia in 2013. The 2015 Academy Awards What is racial atmosphere and climate? A US example that is also global could help clarify these vague ideas, provided that it is understood beforehand that in this context, as in most public references to "race," ‘racial” means “pertaining to racism.” From beginning to end, the 2015 Academy Awards ceremony hit racist notes that slid by unchecked, because it was an occasion of celebration. Neil Patrick Harris, the host, began with what might have been a critical remark about the lack of racial diversity among audience members and award winners: “Tonight we honor Hollywood’s best and whitest, sorry, bright est.” For those who were uncomfortable with the lack of robust racial diversity among audience members and award winners, his remark might have validated their unease. But those who would have been uncomfortable with more racial diversity may have been heard “best and whitest” as support for their social values. (The discourse of white privilege as a critique of contemporary anti-nonwhite racism is, as indicated, that kind of double-edged sword.) Midway through the ceremony, Patricia Arquette called for people of color and members of the lesbian, bisexual, gay, and transgender (LBGT) community to support legislation for equal pay for women and to commit themselves to supporting women, thereby overlooking the women who were either or both people of color and members of the LGВТ community. This kind of oversight may perhaps be excused by Arquette’s ignorance of what academics have been for decades analyzing as “intersectionality.” But Sean Penn’s remark at the grand finale awarding for Best Picture to Alejandro Gonzalez Inarritu, the Mexican director of Birdman, was simply, explicitly, racist: "Who gave this son of a bitch a green card?” Inarritu later brushed off the insult by saying he found it "hilarious,” because “Sean and I have that kind of brutal relationship. I think it was very funny.”20 Inarritu attempt at a “save” for Penn does not address the impact of Penn’s insult on other Mexicans and Mexican Americans, including those without green cards who struggle to remain employed in the face of anti-immigrant prejudice and discrimination. (That such a moment of maximum recognition was brought so low by a racist crack is not unusual in US culture, where the nastiest forms of racist insult are often let loose on people of color who have succeeded.) As a spectacle watched by almost thirty-four million, the 2015 Oscars, despite ratings lower than recent years, was a global public event.21 Symbolically, it has no peer for the display of beauty, talent, and artistic creativity. Its subtext inevitably has implications about current American race relations, which influence their future. The racial implications of the Oscars replays in millions of minds at countless other public celebrations and entertainment venues, as well as in private interactions (for a year at least). Such spectacles are forms of public discourse and what they represent or fail to represent about US racial demographics and the attitude of the dominant white group creates or augments a specific racial climate that in 2015 is part of a more general racial atmosphere of ambiguity and indeterminacy. At the 2015 Academy Awards, for many critical observers, the issue or subject pertaining to race (insofar as it is understood that subjects of race are subjects of racism), was recognition.22 The beauty, talent, and artistic creativity of people of color was not fully recognized. Some people of color did get awards and some audience members were people of color, so recognition, along with diversity, was not completely absent. But there appeared to be insufficient racial diversity for audience and award winners to be considered racially integrated. And that appearance was symbolic.
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
However, the symbolic meaning is ambiguous: Were there people of color who were deserving of awards but did not get them because they were people of color? Is race a factor in who I becomes a member of the Academy of Motion Picture Arts and Sciences? In the future, will the racial makeup of award winners become more or less representative of their proportions in the motion picture industry? If the proportion of people of color in the motion picture industry is not proportional to their presence in the population at large, why is that? The answers to these questions are undetermined in the symbolic spectacle of the 2015 Academy Awards. The observer does not know if recognition of the achievements of people of color in the movie industry will improve, stay the same, or get worse, and she does not know how to find out. The racial (i.e., in regards to racism) climate of the Academy Awards is cloudy, subject to many different interpretations, some of them conflicting. It is an epistemologically unstable racial climate, because people of color do not know what the weather is in that climate, as a basis for prediction, and neither do they know how to find out. The shared judgment throughout the American atmosphere of race in the early twenty-first century is that racism is morally bad . This judgment is a general principle that leaves the nature of racism undefined throughout the atmosphere and most of the climates and subclimates of race. The overriding shared judgment is a bitter and ineffective refuge for nonwhites, because it does not protect them from either First Amendment-protected racist expressions or actions that turn out to be indirectly racist. Energetic self-aware racist whites can try to evade the judgment that they are racist through coded language for racial difference, and the use of intermediate activities and traits as subjects of direct action. That is, something other than race, which nonetheless does a good job of picking out members of a specific racial group, can be used instead of the race of that group to maintain prejudice and legitimize discrimination. The term “racial climate” has a history of meaning “micro-aggressions” based on race , small cuts, insults, and slights that can have a cumulative effect of individual harm.24 In using the term “racial atmosphere,” reference may be made to other issues of harm to people of color, such as ignorance of black history and contemporary racism or discrimination in career advancement.25 The implication of these meanings is that the micro-aggressions add up to what is perceived as a general predisposition of white people to treat people of color in unjust ways. But, at this time, ideas of racial atmosphere and climate also work as metaphors for what is unknown about race relations and attitudes; they capture the vagueness and unpredictability of racial prejudice and discrimination that occur in a society where nonwhites remain disadvantaged, even though there is formal equality. This “vague weather” aspect of atmosphere and climate is an epistemological condition of indecision that may or may not constitute a lasting crisis, although some syndromes of political injustice should be viewed as crises. A crisis is a period of indecision and uncertainty that requires a resolution before life can go on. Will blacks and other people of color achieve more equality with whites, or is the United States—and with it the world, because US racism is exported with business practices, tour-ism, and entertainment products—on the brink of a new era of explicitlу direct oppression of people of color? Are most white Americans, whose race-neutral economic and social activities have racist effects on nonwhites, genuinely ignorant of how the system in which they operate works, or are they secretly but knowingly hearts-and-minds not clear that this indeterminate aspect of present racial atmosphere and climates must be resolved now. We do not know if life can go on if it is not resolved or what it means for life to go on, or not. We do not even know if the putative crisis can be resolved at this time, because there is as yet no systematic and sustained, impassioned, liberatory dis- course for our condition of ambiguity, a time with a black president and police killing with impunity of unarmed black youth, a time of voting rights for everyone but new restrictions and requirements that disproportionately affect African Americans.26 Except for what academics write and say and how important they think their discourse is (among themselves), American discourse of racial liberation is at a standstill . And insofar as academic discourse is uttered and received in a closed system , with a semicaptive audience and no reliable means for it to affect the real world , that standstill remains at the disposal of history, where history is understood to be the unpredictable result of contingent events . However, if academic oppositional political discourse can be related to a longer historical trend, a more coherent and optimistic picture might emerge. Cornel West's ideas about the American black prophetic tradition appears to be a relation to such a trend. Criticisms of security are incapable of reconfiguring securitization discourses – disconnection from empirical study renders them impotent Hyde –Price in 01 (Adrian Hyde-Price, Professor in the Institute for German Studies @ University of Birmingham, Europe’s New Security Challenges, 2001. p. 38-39) Another conceptual innovation from the Copenhagen school—one associated in particular with Ole Wæver—is the notion of securitization. This concept has been presented as the solution to the problems involved in broadening the
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
definition of security without thereby robbing it of its analytical utility . Wæver and his colleagues start from the assumption that security is not a concept with a fixed meaning or a determinate social condition. Security, in other words, cannot be objectively defined . Rather, they argue that it constitutes a distinctive form of politics. To securitize an issue means to take it out of the normal realm of political discourse and to signal a need for it to be addressed urgently and with exceptional means. Moreover, security is not just any threat or problem. Rather, security issues are “existential threats to a referent object by a securitizing actor who thereby generates endorsement of emergency measures beyond rules that would otherwise bind” Securitization thus focuses almost exclusively on the discursive domain and eschews any attempt to determine empirically what constitutes security concerns. It does not aspire to comment on the reality behind a securitization discourse or on the appropriate instruments for tackling security problems . Instead , It suggests that security studies - or what Wæver calls securitization studies - should focus on the discursive moves whereby issues are securitized . The Copenhagen school thus emphasizes the need to understand the “speech acts” that accomplish a process of securitization. Their focus is on the linguistic and conceptual dynamics involved, even though they recognize the importance of the institutional setting within which securitization takes place. The concept of securitization offers some important insights for security studies. However, it is too epistemologically restricted to contribute to a significant retooling of security studies . On the positive side, it draws attention to the way in which security agendas are constructed by politicians and other political actors. It also indicates the utility of discourse analysis as an additional tool of analysis for security studies. However , at best, securitization studies can constitute one aspect of security studies. It cannot provide the foundations for a paradigm shift in the subdiscipline. Its greatest weakness is its epistemological hypochondria, that is , its tendency to reify epistemological problems and push sound observations about knowledge claims to their logical absurdity. Although it is important to understand the discursive moves involved in perceptions of security in, say, the Middle East, it is also necessary to make some assess ment of nondiscursive factors like the military balance or access to freshwater supplies. For the Copenhagen school, however, these nondiscursive factors are relegated to second place. They are considered only to the extent that they facilitate or impede the speech act. In this way, the Copenhagen school is in danger of cutting security studies off from serious empirical research and setting it adrift on a sea of floating signifiers . Rejecting legal engagement unleashes the worst forms of violence. Barnett 10 – Clive Barnett, Faculty of Social Sciences and Reader in Human Geography at The Open University, “PUBLICS AND MARKETS: What’s Wrong With Neoliberalism?”, The Handbook of Social Geography, Ed. Smith, Marston, Pain, and Jones III, http://www.open.ac.uk/socialsciences/emergentpublics/publications/barnett_publicsandmarkets.pdf In accepting the same simplistic opposition between individual freedom and social justice presented by Hayek, but simply reversing the evaluation of the two terms, critics of neoliberalism end up present ing highly moralistic forms of analysis of contemporary political processes . In resisting the idealization of the market as the embodiment of public virtue, they end up embracing an equally idealized view of the forum as the alternative figure of collective life (see Elster 1986). For example, while Harvey insists that neoliberalism is a process driven by the aim of restoring class power, he ends his analysis by arguing that it is the anti- democratic character of neoliberalism that should be the focal point of opposition (Harvey 2005, 205-206). But it is far from clear whether the theories of neoliberalism and neoliberalization developed by political economists, sometimes with the help of governmentality studies, can contribute to reconstructing a theory and practice of radical democratic justice. In Harvey’s analysis, the withdrawal of the state is taken for granted , and leads to the destruction of previous solidarities, unleashing pathologies of anomie, anti-social behaviour and criminality (ibid, 81). In turn, the vacuum created by the withdrawal of the state leads to social solidarities being reconstructed around other axes, of religion and morality, associationism, and nationalism. What has been described as the rise of the “movement society”, expressed in the proliferation of contentious politics of rights-based struggles and identity politics, Harvey sees as one aspect of a spread of corrosive social forms triggered by the rolling-back of states. In the wake of this roll ing- back “[e]verything from gangs and criminal cartels, narco-traffick ing networks, mini-mafias and favela bosses, through community, grassroots and non-governmental organizations, to secular cults and religious sects
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
proliferate” (ibid, 171). These are alternative social forms “that fill the void left behind as state , powers, political parties and other institutional forms are actively dismantled or simply wither away as centres of collective endeavour and of social bonding” (ibid.). What’s really wrong with neoliberalism, for critics who have constructed it as a coherent object of analysis, is the unleashing of destructive pathologies through the combined withdrawal of the state and the unfettered growth of market exchange. ‘Individual freedom’ is presented as a medium of uninhibited hedonism, which if given too much free reign undermines the ascetic virtues of self-denial upon which struggles for ‘social justice’ are supposed to depend. Underwritten by simplistic moral denunciations of ‘the market’ , these theories cover over a series of analytic, explanatory , and normative questions . In the case of both the Marxist narrative of neoliberalization, and the Foucauldian analysis of neoliberal governmentality, it remains unclear whether either tradition can provide adequate resources for thinking about the practical problems of democracy, rights and social justice . This is not helped by the systematic denigration in both lines of thought of ‘liberalism’, a catch-all term used with little discrimination . There is a tendency to present neoliberalism as the natural end-point or rolling-out of a longer tradition of liberal thought – an argument only sustainable through the implicit invocation of some notion of a liberal ‘episteme’ covering all varieties and providing a core of meaning. One of the lessons drawn by diverse strands of radical political theory from the experience of twentieth-century history is that struggles for social justice can create new forms of domination and inequality. It is this that leads to a grudging appreciation of liberalism as a potential source for insight into the politics of pluralistic associational life. The cost of the careless disregard for ‘actually existing liberalisms’ is to remain blind to the diverse strands of egalitarian thought about the relationships between democracy, rights and social justice that one finds in, for example: post-Rawslian political philosophy; post-Habermasian theories of democracy, including their feminist variants; various postcolonial liberalisms; the flowering of agonistic liberalisms and theories of radical democracy; and the revival of republican theories of democracy, freedom, and justice. No doubt theorists of neoliberalism would see all this as hopelessly trapped within the ‘neoliberal frame’ of individualism, al though if one takes this argument to its logical conclusion, even Marx’s critique of capitalist exploitation, dependent as it is on an ideal of self-ownership, is nothing more than a variation on Lockean i ndividual rights.
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
2NC
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
2NC---FW BUT their focus on themselves and her investment into the topic in this space is worse for community formation, reifies trauma, and actively strengthens anti-Asian structures by marginalizing the Asian people who were never “in this space” to begin with Táíwò, 20 —assistant professor of philosophy at Georgetown University (Olúfémi, “Being-in-the-Room Privilege: Elite Capture and Epistemic Deference,” The Philosopher, vol. 108, no. 4, dml) I think it’s less about the core ideas and more about the prevailing norms that convert them into practice. The call to “listen to the most affected” or “centre the most marginalized” is ubiquitous in many academic and activist circles. But it’s never sat well with me. In my experience, when people say they need to listen to the most affected ”, it isn’t because they intend to set up Skype calls to refugee camps or to collaborate with houseless people . Instead, it has more often meant handing conversational authority and attentional goods to those who most snugly fit into the social categories associated with these ills – regardless of what they actually do or do not know , or what they have or have not personally experienced . In the case of my conversation with Helen, my racial category tied me more “authentically” to an experience that neither of us had had. She was called to defer to me by the rules of the game as we understood it. Even where stakes are high – where potential researchers are discussing how to understand a social phenomenon, where activists are deciding what to target – these rules often prevail. The trap wasn’t that standpoint epistemology was affecting the conversation, but how. Broadly, the norms of putting standpoint epistemology into practice call for practices of deference : giving offerings , passing the mic , believing . These are good ideas in many cases, and the norms that ask us to be ready to do them stem from admirable motivations: a desire to increase the social power of marginalized people identified as sources of knowledge and rightful targets of deferential behaviour. But deferring in this way as a rule or default political orientation can actually work counter to marginalized groups’ interests, especially in elite spaces . Some rooms have outsize power and influence : the Situation Room, the newsroom, the bargaining table, the conference room. Being in these rooms means being in a position to affect institutions and broader social dynamics by way of deciding what one is to say and do. Access to these rooms is itself a kind of social advantage , and one often gained through some prior social advantage. From a societal standpoint, the “ most affected ” by the social injustices we associate with politically important identities like gender, class, race, and nationality are disproportionately likely to be incarcerated, underemployed, or part of the 44 percent of the world’s population without internet access – and thus both left out of the rooms of power and largely ignored by the people in the rooms of power . Individuals who make it past the various social selection pressures that filter out those social identities associated with these negative outcomes are most likely to be in the room. That is, they are most likely to be in the room precisely because of ways in which they are systematic ally different from (and thus potentially unrepresentative of) the very people they are then asked to represent in the room . I suspected that Helen’s offer was a trap. She was not the one who set it, but it threatened to ensnare us both all the same. Broader cultural norms – the sort set in motion by prefacing statements with “As a Black man…” – cued up a set of standpoint-respecting practices that many of us know consciously or unconsciously by rote. However, the forms of deference that often follow are ultimately self- undermining and only reliably serve “ elite capture ”: the control over political agendas and resources
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
by a group’s most advantaged people. If we want to use standpoint epistemology to challenge unjust power arrangements, it’s hard to imagine how we could do worse . To say what’s wrong with the popular, deferential applications of standpoint epistemology, we need to understand what makes it popular. A number of cynical answers present themselves: some (especially the more socially advantaged) don’t genuinely want social change – they just want the appearance of it. Alternatively, deference to figures from oppressed communities is a performance that sanitizes, apologizes for, or simply distracts from the fact that the deferrer has enough “in the room” privilege for their “lifting up” of a perspective to be of consequence. I suspect there is some truth to these views, but I am unsatisfied. Many of the people who support and enact these deferential norms are rather like Helen: motivated by the right reasons, but trusting people they share such rooms with to help them find the proper practical expression of their joint moral commitments. We don’t need to attribute bad faith to all or even most of those who interpret standpoint epistemology deferentially to explain the phenomenon, and it’s not even clear it would help. Bad “roommates” aren’t the problem for the same reason that Helen being a good roommate wasn’t the solution: the problem emerges from how the rooms themselves are constructed and managed. To return to the initial example with Helen, the issue wasn’t merely that I hadn’t grown up in the kind of low-income, redlined community she was imagining. The epistemic situation was much worse than this. Many of the facts about me that made my life chances different from those of the people she was imagining were the very same facts that made me likely to be offered things on their behalf. If I had grown up in such a community, we probably wouldn’t have been on the phone together. Many aspects of our social system serve as filtering mechanisms, determining which interactions happen and between whom, and thus which social patterns people are in a position to observe. For the majority of the 20th century, the U.S. quota system of immigration made legal immigration with a path to citizenship almost exclusively available to Europeans (earning Hitler’s regard as the obvious “leader in developing explicitly racist policies of nationality and immigration”). But the 1965 Immigration and Nationality Act opened up immigration possibilities, with a preference for “skilled labour”. My parents’ qualification as skilled labourers does much to explain their entry into the country and the subsequent class advantages and monetary resources (such as wealth) that I was born into. We are not atypical: the Nigerian-American population is one of the country’s most successful immigrant populations (what no one mentions, of course, is that the 112,000 or so Nigerian-Americans with advanced degrees is utterly dwarfed by the 82 million Nigerians who live on less than a dollar a day, or how the former fact intersects with the latter). The selectivity of immigration law helps explain the rates of educational attainment of the Nigerian diasporic community that raised me, which in turn helps explain my entry into the exclusive Advanced Placement and Honours classes in high school, which in turn helps explain my access to higher education...and so on, and so on. It is easy, then, to see how this deferential form of standpoint epistemology contributes to elite capture at scale . The rooms of power and influence are at the end of causal chains that have selection effects . As you get higher and higher forms of education , social experiences narrow – some students are pipelined to PhDs and others to prisons . Deferential ways of dealing with identity can inherit the distortions caused by these selection processes . But it’s equally easy to see locally – in this room, in this academic literature or field, in this conversation – why this deference seems to make sense. It is often an improvement on the epistemic procedure that preceded it: the person deferred to may well be better epistemically positioned than the others in the room. It may well be the best we can do while holding fixed most of the facts about the rooms themselves: what power resides in them, who is admitted . But these are the last facts we should want to hold fixed . Doing better than the epistemic norms we’ve inherited from a history of explicit global apartheid is an awfully low bar to set. The facts that explain who ends up in which room shape our world much more powerfully than the squabbles for comparative prestige between people who have already made it into the rooms. And when the conversation is about social justice, the mechanisms of the social system that determine who gets into which room often just are the parts of society we aim to address . For example, the fact that incarcerated people cannot participate in academic discussions about freedom that physically take place on campus is intimately related to the fact that they are locked in cages. Deference epistemology marks itself as a solution to an epistemic and political problem. But not only does it fail to solve these problems, it adds new ones . One might think questions of justice ought to be
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
primarily concerned with fixing disparities around health care , working conditions , and basic material and interpersonal security . Yet conversations about justice have come to be shaped by people who have ever more specific practical advice about fixing the distribution of attention and conversational power . Deference practices that serve attention-focused campaigns (e.g. we’ve read too many white men, let’s now read some people of colour) can fail on their own highly questionable terms: attention to spokespeople from marginalized groups could , for example, direct attention away from the need to change the social system that marginalizes them. Elites from marginalized groups can benefit from this arrangement in ways that are compatible with social progress. But treating group elites’ interests as necessarily or even presumptively aligned with full group interests involves a political naiveté we cannot afford. Such treatment of elite interests functions as a racial Reaganomics : a strategy reliant on fantasies about the exchange rate between the attention economy and the material economy . Perhaps the lucky few who get jobs finding the most culturally authentic and cosmetically radical description of the continuing carnage are really winning one for the culture . Then, after we in the chattering class get the clout we deserve and secure the bag , its contents will eventually trickle down to the workers who clean up after our conferences , to slums of the Global South’s megacities , to its countryside . But probably not . A fuller and fairer assessment of what is going on with deference and standpoint epistemology would go beyond technical argument, and contend with the emotional appeals of this strategy of deference. Those in powerful rooms may be “elites” relative to the larger group they represent, but this guarantees nothing about how they are treated in the rooms they are in. After all, a person privileged in an absolute sense (a person belonging to, say, the half of the world that has secure access to “basic needs”) may nevertheless feel themselves to be consistently on the low end of the power dynamics they actually experience. Deference epistemology responds to real, morally weighty experiences of being put down, ignored, sidelined, or silenced. It thus has an important non-epistemic appeal to members of stigmatized or marginalized groups: it intervenes directly in morally consequential practices of giving attention and respect . The social dynamics we experience have an outsize role in developing and refining our political subjectivity, and our sense of ourselves. But this very strength of standpoint epistemology – its recognition of the importance of perspective – becomes its weakness when combined with deferential practical norms . Emphasis on the ways we are marginalized often matches the world as we have experienced it. But, from a structural perspective, the rooms we never needed to enter (and the explanations of why we can avoid these rooms) might have more to teach us about the world and our place in it. If so, the deferential approach to standpoint epistemology actually prevents centring ” or even hearing from the most marginalized; it focuses us on the interaction of the rooms we occupy , rather than calling us to account for the interactions we don’t experience . This fact about who is in the room, combined with the fact that speaking for others generates its own set of important problems (particularly when they are not there to advocate for themselves), eliminates pressures that might otherwise trouble the centrality of our own suffering – and of the suffering of the marginalized people that do happen to make it into rooms with us. The dangers with this feature of deference politics are grave , as are the risks for those outside of the most powerful rooms. For those who are deferred to , it can supercharge group-undermining norms . In
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
Conflict is Not Abuse, Sarah Schulman makes a provocative observation about the psychological effects of both trauma and felt superiority : while these often come about for different reasons and have very different moral statuses, they result in similar behavioural patterns. Chief among these are misrepresenting the stakes of conflict (often by overstating harm ) or representing others’ independence as a hostile threat ( such as failures to centre ” the right topics or people ). These behaviours, whatever their causal history, have corrosive effects on individuals who perform them as well as the groups around them, especially when a community’s norms magnify or multiply these behaviours rather than constraining or metabolizing them . For those who defer , the habit can supercharge moral cowardice . The norms provide social cover for the abdicat ion of responsibility : it displaces onto individual heroes , a hero class, or a mythicized past the work that is ours to do now in the present. Their perspective may be clearer on this or that specific matter , but their overall point of view isn’t any less particular or constrained by history than ours . More importantly, deference places the accountability that is all of ours to bear onto select people – and, more often than not, a hyper-sanitized and thoroughly fictional caricature of them . The same tactics of deference that insulate us from criticism also insulate us from connection and transformation . They prevent us from engaging empathetically and authentically with the struggles of other people prerequisites of coalitional politics. As identities become more and more fine-grained and disagreements sharper , we come to realize that “ coalitional politics (understood as struggle across difference ) is, simply, politics . Thus, the deferential orientation, like that fragmentation of political collectivity it enables, is ultimately anti-political . Deference rather than interdependence may soothe short-term psychological wounds . But it does so at a steep cost : it can undermine the epistemic goals that motivate the project, and it entrenches a politics unbefitting of anyone fighting for freedom rather than for privilege , for collective liberation rather than mere parochial advantage . Disarm is complete Collins Dictionary N.D. [Collins Dictionary, “Disarm”, English Dictionary, https://www.collinsdictionary.com/us/dictionary/english/disarm] disarm Word forms: disarms 3rd person singular present tense, disarming present participle, disarmed past tense past participle 1. transitive verb To disarm a person or group means to take away all their weapons . We will agree to disarming troops and leaving their weapons at military positions. 2. intransitive verb If a country or group disarms, it gives up the use of weapons, especially nuc lear weapon s. There was still a chance that international pressure would force the country to disarm.
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
3. transitive verb If a person or their behavior disarms you, they cause you to feel less angry, hostile, or critical toward them. His unease disarmed her. Disarming nuclear forces requires abolition , NOT mere trimming . Mello 15 , [Greg Mello is a co-founder of the Los Alamos Study Group and has led its varied activities since 1989, which have included policy research, environmental analysis, congressional education and lobbying, community organizing, litigation, advertising, and the nuts and bolts of running a small nonprofit. From time to time Greg has served as a consulting analyst and writer for other nuclear policy organizations. Greg was originally educated as an engineer (Harvey Mudd College, 1971) and regional planner (Harvard, 1975). Greg led the first environmental enforcement at Los Alamos National Laboratory. He was a hydrogeologist for the New Mexico Environment Department and later a consultant to industry. In 2002 Greg was a Visiting Research Fellow at Princeton's Program on Science and Global Security, Bulletin 206: Desultory NPT conference ends in division, a good thing; 108 countries pledge to help ban nuclear weapons, https://lasg.org/ActionAlerts/Bulletin206.html] All these NNWSs joined an NPT regime which requires the five original NWSs (the “P5,” so-called because they are also the permanent members of the UN Security Council) to disarm. They haven’t, they aren’t, and they won’t even discuss substantive disarmament steps with each other, let alone in the NPT context, although they drone endlessly about a “step-by- step” or “building blocks” approach to disarmam ent . But as to actually taking one of these steps – well, that’s something else , isn’t it? (See for example “US Policies Belie Claims of Article VI Compliance;” here’s a slightly longer version of the same article. For the larger picture, documented in detail for all the nuclear weapon states, see Assuring Destruction Forever: 2015 Edition). For our members and donors we should say that the Study Group was well represented at this RevCon. As mentioned in Bulletin 204, we wrote the chapter on modernization of US nuclear weapons in Assuring Destruction Forever and co-wrote the book’s introduction. Our “Ban the Bomb, Save the Planet: a Perspective from within a Nuclear-Armed State,” was in the conference- opening issue of NPT News in Review. “US Policies Belie Claims of Article VI Compliance” rebutted the specious State Department claim that the US is disarming. Thank you for the opportunity to provide these materials. We really got about the best outcome from the RevCon we could have hoped for We think the outcome of this conference was not just upbeat, but about the best anyone could have reasonably hoped for. Why? First, there was no final consensus document. That’s very good, because these negotiated consensus documents (sometimes produced, sometimes not) have been a waste of time for anyone seeking nuclear disarmament. Harsh words? Well, look at the record. What has been their effect? None. It was always a given that no worthwhile document would emerge in 2015 given a) the consensus process required, b) the complete intransigence of the nuclear weapon states regarding nuclear disarmament, and c) the unwillingness of the U.S. and some of its allies to even discuss the Israeli nuclear arsenal, let alone convene a conference under conditions which any single state (i.e. Israel) could not veto, to talk about a possible nuclear weapons free zone in the Middle East, a consensus commitment of 2010 and a major concern running back to 1995 at least. The enormous contrast between how Israel’s advanced nuclear arsenal is treated by the US and its allies and how the Article IV right to peaceful nuclear technologies is treated in the case of Iran would be hardly credible as fiction, were it written before the state of Israel and its supporters gained such a powerful hold on US foreign policy and elections. Essentially none of the many disarmament promises wrung out of the P5 at successive RevCons have been kept. Why bother with a new set? (See the un-actioned 1995 “Resolution on the Middle East,” the un-implemented “Thirteen Practical Steps” of 2000, and the 64-point “Action Plan” of 2010, the general lack of implementation of which has been reviewed in detail by year and topic by RCW.) The P5, led by the US and its allies, have by this point so damaged the credibility of the NPT regime that a new set of empty promises can hardly repair it. Something more is needed. The lack of a consensus outcome makes this reality quite clear, which we must deem a very positive event. Rebecca Johnson of the Acronym Institute, an astute longtime diplomatic observer and participant, sums up the P5-created NPT crisis in an analysis of this RevCon. The five nuclear armed states within the treaty have taken it [the NPT] for granted as their political fiefdom, acting as if its extension in 1995 has legitimized them to possess and deploy nuclear weapons indefinitely as long as they engage in diplomatic rituals of public criticism every five years. Meanwhile, the four nuclear-armed states outside the NPT continue to benefit [by NPT- based scrutiny of geopolitical adversaries and NPT-based nuclear abstention by 186 countries] without paying any membership dues. An egregious example was set by the US nuclear deals brokered by the Bush administration with India a few years after that non-NPT state conducted nuclear tests and declared itself a "nuclear weapon state". And now comes this week's decision by the US, UK and Canada to sacrifice the chance of a consensus 2015 NPT outcome for the sake of Israel, another nuclear-armed non-NPT state. Second, the way the consensus collapsed was revealing – and revolting. A nuclear weapon state not even party to the treaty was able to spike five years of preparatory diplomacy and a month-long negotiating conference? The US and UK cared so little about this conference they were ready to throw its negotiations away at the last second to show their support for Israel and its nuclear arsenal? Really? And this, while the nuclear nonproliferation regime in the Middle East is poised to collapse further, not because of Iran but rather because of Saudi Arabia, which is hinting that it might want to buy nuclear weapons from Pakistan with or without Pakistani forces to deliver them? The sudden exertion of domineering power by the US and its allies in support of nuclear double standards was particularly shocking – and hopefully clarifying – for all who seek a Middle East nuclear weapons free zone. Such hopes are vain as long as the basic question of the legitimacy and legality of nuclear remains unsettled. The P5, no doubt with variations that need not concern us, claim the NPT gives their nuclear arsenals special legitimacy. This is an aspect, and not the only one, of the so-called “legal gap” that allows certain states to legitimately, they think, threaten the whole world with nuclear weapons. That legal gap will remain open to the extent it is not closed – by treaty. The nuclear weapon states will certainly not close it. The only process that will close that gap is the negotiation of, and gradual accession by more and more states to, a nuclear weapons ban treaty, which prohibits and stigmatizes the possession and use of nuclear weapons. It is a ban-shaped gap. Of course a ban treaty cannot force states to disarm their nuclear arsenals, but it can outlaw the failure to do so, with significant implications internationally and domestically. It is probably also the only way to save the NPT nonproliferation regime, based as it is on the norm of nuclear non-possession, which the nuclear weapon states continue to erode both in practice and in rhetoric. In the final analysis diplomats, like the rest of us, are personally responsible for what they say and do. Rose Gottemoeller, the Under Secretary of State for Arms Control and International Security, works in an administration that has disarmed less and is modernizing more than any prior post-Cold War administration. She is also personally responsible for spiking consensus at this RevCon. Like Obama, Ms. Gottemoeller had a liberal arms control reputation before this job. Like Obama, she is now implementing an opposite agenda. Third, and most important as already noted, a majority of world’s states have now formally associated themselves with efforts to prohibit the possession and use of nuclear weapons based on their fundamental immorality, their incompatibility with humanitarian law and the principles underlying it, and the risk nuclear weapons pose for “the very survival of humanity,” as expressed in the Humanitarian Pledge. This movement is growing, intelligent, well-organized, young, less male-dominated than usual, has a clear and achievable objective, and it is not based in the US or hostage to US funders, all of which are strong points. To sum up, for these three reasons we think this “failed” conference is an excellent milestone or coming-of-age in what could be a new disarmament era, with new structures, organizations, people, and a new framing of the issues. Above all what is different is that the US – neither the US government nor the largely-captive nonprofit-academic complex through which it frequently acts – does not control this movement. What is new and upbeat will not be understood in Washington, but that’s fine. The upbeat note of the Humanitarian Pledge is unlikely to be heard or understood in Washington, DC. That is because this note comes in a new key, a frequency inaudible in official Washington and likely to remain that way for the foreseeable future, precisely because it threatens the nuclear status quo. And not just that, but through that, it threatens to some extent the identity, prestige and therefore the power of the US government internationally and even, nota bene, domestically. All of these are at present deeply associated with nuclear weapons. Nuclear weapons, unchallenged, remain potent status markers in the world system and key elements of national identity. The humanitarian frame of reference threatens all that. It attempts to re-place respect for the human person as a hallmark of legitimate power. It discredits threatened mass destruction as an instrument of statecraft. Overt threats of mass destruction emanating from the “legal gap” mentioned legitimate lesser forms of violence for political and business leaders and in societies, including forms of structural violence. Such structural violence, conveyed economically and amplified by political corruption, resource exhaustion, and environmental collapse, is a terrible reality that affects billions already. It is war by other means. The fact that this new note is “inaudible” in Washington does not mean it is ineffectual. At present, official Washington is ignoring quite a few important new realities external to itself and its self-conception of power, the very definition of hubris. New realities in international relations, in the environment, in resources and economics, in society – to pick a few – are not less real and powerful just because official Washington cannot as yet understand them or act responsibly. There are any number of things Washington doesn’t understand and won’t, until change is forced from the outside, in a new key, magisterially. That is just how it is for this country now. It appears to us at the Study Group (as it does to most other Americans) that the capital of this country is functionally bewildered, trapped on a fundraising treadmill no one knows how to stop, and lost in its own propaganda, ideologies, and power games. It is obviously extremely corrupt. Many congresspersons could be diagnosed as sociopaths, as one experienced criminal psychologist we know confidently assures us. Washington is always hard of hearing where self-interest is not the dominant note. But it will respond, in some lame way, when there are no other options. We say this even though we spend a fair amount of time in Washington and do really treasure our professional and personal friendships there. Official Washington will probably never consciously realize or admit that nuclear weapons cannot be used in war without unacceptable risks, have no military value whatsoever, and are inherently immoral. Neither does Washington recognize that these facts – and that’s what they are, facts – and others that follow from them create a cascade of military, management, and political implications that no legislation or policy can ever fully mitigate. Those implications are however very real and they must be faced in practical terms, with or without understanding. Why there are so many problems in maintaining and modernizing nuclear forces? The US government has commissioned hundreds of studies addressing aspects of that problem and is no closer to answers. All the real answers, the rational ones that could work, are off the table before the studies even begin. The notion that the nuclear weapons enterprise, taken as a whole and in its several parts, is incompatible with human aspirations and with the mores of the society in which it is embedded –with those of any society or civilization – does not occur to official Washington except in whispers. In Washington the “warheads” reign, proclaiming in a hundred ways at breakfast speeches, in learned think-tanks and in congressional hearings, “L’etat, c’est moi.”[i] Saying so does not however make it true. Neither does it pay the bills. To paraphrase Shakespeare’s Henry V, “Canst thou, when thou command'st [the economy],/ Command the health of it?” On that, all depends. The inability of official Washington and some of its captive NGOs to process the import of a ban treaty comes down to something very simple: Washington policymakers cannot conceive of not being in charge, not just of the US but of the world. Such thoughts kill careers and must be kept at bay.[ii] All this is to say that the ban process is not just about nuclear weapons. It’s also about power and initiative in world affairs – who has it, and who does not. The ban process, as opposed to other hypothetical disarmament paths ( steps , building blocks ,
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
comprehensive binding disarmament treaties, and all other processes which nuclear weapon states can veto) is about who decides whether nuclear weapons are legitimate. The NPT supposedly makes nuclear weapons illegitimate. But unlike the enforcement provisions imposed on non-nuclear signatories, there are no enforcement provisions for NWSs, and so the NPT divides the world into two classes of states as far as nuclear weapons and technologies are concerned. This structure provides potent reasons for the US in particular to nuclearize international discourse whenever possible in any of several ways, casting diplomacy into channels comfortable for the exertion of US power. So the NPT, instead of being a disarmament treaty that sooner or later applies equally to all states, has become in many ways a geopolitical hammer permanently available to those very few NPT NWSs with the means and motive to use it, i.e. the US and its allies. That is, the existing NPT regime is also very much about power. It was the misuse and inequitable distortion of the world’s nonproliferation regime in favor of one or two states, including one – Israel – that perennially contravenes international law and has refused to even acknowledge its nuclear arsenal, that was the reef on which this RevCon wrecked. Washington will never decide to disarm its nuclear forces . Trim – yes; disarm, no. What Washington cannot conceive are decisions forced upon it by intransigent circumstances or independent sovereignties. But these exist. Great natural disasters, economic disasters, defeats in war, ecological disasters – these are not subject to the vanity of this or any Congress. Neither can the US control the world. That sounds obvious but it’s not, not in Washington, where Wolfowitz’s disastrous 1992 Draft Defense Planning Guidance (whole text here) has been the more or less the guiding policy, more evidently in some periods than in others. It’s a failing policy of course, and accordingly this a very dangerous moment for the world. In the years since 1992 American wars and proxy wars have already been fatal to millions.
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
1NR
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
1NR---PIC It IS real world in a tactics testing strategy Reynolds 23 [Keis Reynolds who is on the In These Times board of directors, is also a freelance writer. “You Can’t Organize Alone” MAY 31, 2023, https://inthesetimes.com/article/gain-by-gathering-mariame- kaba-chicago-political-education]//sripad That tradition of political education , of learning together , is something our movements dearly need to recover . Over the past two years, parts of our movements have become stagnant as organizers contend with burnout and groups struggle to replenish their ranks . It often feels like we’ve forgotten the importance of political education, for both new and existing members . Some of us have also forgotten that our work includes a lifelong commitment to learning not just from texts , but from study groups and book clubs, workshops and teach-ins, discussions around dining tables or tucked in library corners . Creating these shared learning moments allows us to sharpen our analyses , evaluate strategies and see how the landscape is changing . As my fellow organizer Santera Matthews says, it “ helps us dream bigger.” That tradition of political education, of learning together, is something our movements dearly need to recover. Without those opportunities, organizing spaces can fall into bad habits . The knowledge of political theory, organizing histories and essential contexts can become a tool for gatekeeping . The work can come to feel transactional . Opportunities for collaboration are lost when curious people are told they don’t need to know X to do Y and Z . Ultimately, members search for new political homes .
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
1NR---DA Disarmament removes the barrier to all conventional conflict and drives defense spending . Leah and Lowther 17, [Christine Leah completed her PhD at the Strategic and Defence Studies Centre of the Australian National University. Previously, she was a summer associate at the RAND Corporation, a research intern at the International Institute for Strategic Studies (IISS) Singapore, the French Ministry of Defense, IISS London, and a research analyst at the Australian Strategic Policy Institute., Adam B. Lowther is Research Professor at the Air Force Research Institute. He received his PhD from the University of Alabama, Tuscaloosa. He is the author of articles in Military Review, Journal of Chinese Political Science, Proceedings, and An Army at War., “Conventional Arms and Nuclear Peace,” Spring 2017, https://www.jstor.org/stable/pdf/26271588.pdf?refreqid=excelsior %3Ada991276a2e0a696b7c79ac449cf3089&ab_segments=&origin=&initiator=&acceptTC=1]//KAK If the past offers any lessons for the future, it is not unreasonable to believe that a world free of nuc lear weapon s is a world in which standing armies grow larger , defense expenditures (as a percentage of gross domestic product) increase , and conflict becomes more frequent as the perceived risks to a nation and its leaders decline . National leaders are not always rational , because they do not effectively weigh costs and benefits or risks and rewards , which would lead them to overvalue the prospect of a loss and undervalue the prospect of a gain. The certain loss caused by any prospective use of nuc lear weapon s has caused decision makers to exercise great restraint when contemplating the prospective use of force.21 History appears to suggest that, to some degree, nuclear weapons do cause decision makers to see the use of nuclear weapons as ensuring losses, with few gains—causing restraint. Thus, eliminating nuc lear weapon s may well reduce perceived risks and increase perceived gains from fighting— making the world safe for conventional conflict . Such a state of affairs would not have the same absolute risk associated with it that nuclear warfare poses (that of total annihilation), but it would increase the risks of proliferating conflict , which may lead to a dramatic increase in conflict-related casualties . Putin’s withholding aggression because of US nuclear deterrence Maurer 22 , [John. D Maurer, Professor at the School of Advanced Air and Space Studies at Air University and a nonresident fellow at the American Enterprise Institute, "Ensuring Nuclear Deterrence in the 21st Century," Ripon Society, https://riponsociety.org/article/ensuring-nuclear-deterrence-in-the- 21st-century/]//KAK Nuclear deterrence has moved back to the center of national security discussions as a result of Putin’s irresponsible threats. Putin’s truly scary behavior reinforces the critical importance of deterring nuclear use by lawless regimes. Fortunately, Putin’s threats come from a place of weakness. Russia is losing the war on the ground to Ukrainian forces backed by Western aid. Putin’s nuclear threats are designed to drive a wedge into the coalition supporting Ukraine. Thus far, they have not succeeded. In fact, Russia’s lack of nuclear use , despite embarrassing losses on the battlefield , shows that on some level deterrence is still working . Many analysts have worried that although the United States and Russia have similar numbers of large “strategic” nuclear weapons, the Russians have several thousand shorter- range “tactical” nuclear weapons, while the United States has only a few hundred. Yet the Russians have struggle d to translate this numerical edge into actual battlefield advantage.
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
If Russia used its large tactical nuclear force indiscriminately, it would risk escalation to total nuclear war with the United States, a war that Russia knows it cannot win . Even using a few tactical nuclear weapons could have significant consequences for the Putin regime . Aside from furthering Russia’s diplomatic and economic isolation, Russian nuclear use might provoke direct NATO attacks on Russia’s weakened military . As a result, Putin has neither used nuc lear weapon s against Ukraine nor widened the conflict to attack NATO countries supplying Ukraine’s military . NATO’s ability to dominate Russia in a conventional conflict, combined with the U nited S tates’ large strategic nuclear arsenal , make nuclear escalation a losing game for the Putin regime . In the short term, the best thing the United States can do in response to Putin’s nuclear threats is continue its support of Ukrainian success on the battlefield.
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help